[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]

On Alleged Flaws of Pancritical Rationalism

by Dmitry Sepety

Zaporizhzhya State Medical University, Ukraine

[email protected]

 

Criticisms of Antoni Diller's criticisms of pancritical rationalism

in the article “On critical and pancritical rationalism”,

forthcoming in the journal Philosophy of the Social Sciences.

 

In the article “On critical and pancritical rationalism”, Antoni Diller criticizes Bartley’s ‘pancritical rationalism’ to show that critical rationalism is superior to it. In this polemical piece I argue that most of these criticisms, as epitomized by Diller on his internet-site (http://www.cantab.net/users/antoni.diller/rationalism/pancritical.html), are mistaken, mostly due to misinterpretation of Bartley’s statements. As important issues of this polemics, I highlight Bartley’s contribution to the development of non-justificationist conception of rationality and discuss an important question of how Popper’s and Bartley’s non-justificationism is (and is not) to be understood.

 

1. Principal Contentions of “Pancritical Rationalism”

My own view is that the question of inferiority/superiority between critical and pancritical rationalism is unfruitful. I think that what Bartley calls ‘pancritical rationalism’ or ‘comprehensively critical rationalism’ is an important contribution to development of critical rationalism. But, it is to be admitted that it was Bartley himself who has provoked the discussion in terms of inferiority/superiority, by his sharp criticism of ‘critical rationalism’ and opposing ‘pancritical rationalism’ to it.

What Bartley’s contribution consists in? It is solution of “the problem of limits of rationality”. As Bartley describes it:

“I was confronting the contention … that there is an essential logical limitation to rationality: the rational defence and examination of ideas must, for logical reasons, be terminated by an arbitrary and irrational appeal to what can be called dogmas or absolute presuppositions.(Bartley 1984, 221)

Bartley’s solution, which he calls “pancritical rationalism” or “comprehensively critical rationalism” may be summarized in three principal contentions:

(1) Non-justificationism: The contention about necessity of dogmas or absolute presuppositions stems from the demand that all our beliefs were justified rationally; this demand entails infinite regress of justifications; it seems that this regress must be broken on some unjustified positions accepted as dogmas. Pancritical rationalism, instead, breaks with the demand of justification and identifies rationality with criticism: “nothing of any interest can be justified in the way required …; criticism is nonetheless possible provided one unfuses justification and criticism” (Bartley 1984, 221);

(2) The solution of the problem of limits of rationality: “there are no limits to rationality in the sense that one must postulate dogmas or presuppositions that must be held exempt from review” (Bartley 1984, 221)

“What I did … was to show that no authorities or justifiers in this sense were needed in criticism. … criticism can be carried out successfully and satisfactorily without … any resort to dogmas or authorities. That is, when I declare that all statements are criticizable, I mean that it is not necessary, in criticism, … to declare a dogma that cannot be criticized…; I mean that it is not necessary to mark off a special class of statements, the justifiers, which do the justifying and criticizing but are not open to criticism…” (Bartley 1984, 223)

In other words,

(2.1) Rationality understood as critical attitude, openness to criticism may be comprehensive: we may hold all positions (including the critical attitude itself) open to critical discussion.

On my view, these principal contentions of pancritical rationalism are right. And I consider their explicit statement and defence as Bartley’s important contribution to the development of critical rationalism. Bartley may well be mistaken on some other, minor points, but this does not afflict the principal contentions of pancritical rationalism, as described above.

And first that is to be noted about Diller’s criticisms of pancritical rationalism is that they do not affect principal contentions of pancritical rationalism at all.

In the following text I confront each principal Diller’s criticism of Bartley, as epitomized on his internet-site, with my rejoinder.

 

2. (Mis)interpreting Critical Rationalism

Diller: “Bartley misinterprets critical rationalism. For him, it is summed up by the principle that any assumption, except this one, which cannot be supported either by argument or experience is to be discarded.”

Rejoinder: Probably, Bartley did partially misinterpret critical rationalism. But Bartley did not describe (in Retreat to Commitment) it in the way Diller attributes to him. Besides, his (mis)interpretation indicates important drawbacks in Popper’s description of critical rationalism in chapter 24 of Open Society and Its Enemies.

Bartley did describe critical rationalism as position whose adherents share three distinctive points (which distinguish critical rationalism from uncritical):

"(1) They concede that rationality is limited in the sense that some matters, such as the principles and standards of rationality, cannot be justified… (2) They claim that this concession is unimportant, or at least not important enough to give any consolation to irrationalism. (3) If challenged, they tend to ground or justify rationalist position in personal or social commitment to standards which are beyond challenge." (Bartley 1984, 97)

Bartley’s own position, pancritical rationalism, share with critical rationalism points (1) and (2); and it strenthens (1) with emphasizing that “nothing of any interest can be justified in the way required”. So, the purported difference is about (3). But it is far from obvious that critical rationalism, in Popper’s description, is really guilty of (3). In Open Society and Its Enemies I find nothing to support unequivocally the charge of (3). So, probably Bartley misinterprets Popper on this point.

Bartley did support his charge by quotation of a fragment from Open Society and Its Enemies where Popper did describe critical rationalism as “minimum concession to irrationalism” (Popper 1957, 232) which admits that the rationalist attitude “is based upon an irrational decision”, “an irrational faith in reason”, − “a critical form of rationalism, one which frankly admits its limitations, and its basis in an irrational decision (and so far, a certain priority of irrationalism).” (Popper 1957, 231)

Bartley have qualified these statements as “obviously fideistic”. Popper did deny this. In 1992, in Kyoto, he did explain that he did mean by “faith” not Faith of fideism, but faith-belief, − “my belief that it is a good attitude to try out, or perhaps to adopt”; so “fideism doesn’t come in”. (Artigas 1999, 30-31)

So far, it seems that Bartley’s criticism of critical rationalism is based on misinterpretation. But there are further complications.

 

In the same speech in Kyoto Popper has made a statement:

“Critical discussion means discussing not attitude or such things, but problems, and solutions of these problems, therefore theories, propositions, positions and so on.” (Artigas 1999, 31)

This statement seems to say unequivocally that (moral) attitudes are not proper objects of critical discussion (which is the same as to say that they are exempt from criticism). If Popper did really mean it (we are to take into account that the speech was impromptu), this strongly supports Bartley’s charge ("If challenged, they tend to ground or justify rationalist position in personal or social commitment to standards which are beyond challenge"). For me, it is incomprehensible how Popper could mean it, − for in Open Society and Its Enemies he did discuss moral attitudes (such as holism, individualism, rationalism, irrationalism) critically. On the other hand, I can not imagine, what else Popper could mean by that statement.

 

Important points of Bartley’s criticisms were that critical rationalism, as described in chapter 24 of Open Society and Its Enemies, 1) with respect to the problem of limits of rationality “Popper’s own explicit first attempt to solve the problem is inadequate” and 2) it “seems to operate within a justificationist context foreign to the dominant themes of his own thought” (Bartley 1984, 104). I think there is much to support these criticisms.

Name “critical rationalism” was introduced by Popper in section 2 of chapter 24 of Open Society and Its Enemies, as an alternative to “uncritical (comprehensive) rationalism”. The last is described as the attitude of accepting “the principle that any assumption which cannot be supported either by argument or by experience is to be discarded”. (Popper 1957, 230).

Popper agrees with irrationalists that “this principle of uncritical rationalism is inconsistent; for since it cannot, in its turn, be supported by argument or by experience, it implies that it should itself be discarded” (Popper 1957, 230). Let us call this problem the specific problem of uncritical rationalism.

Popper also remarks: “This criticism may be generalized. Since all argument must proceed from assumptions, it is plainly impossible to demand that all assumptions should be based on argument” (Popper 1957, 230). Let us call this problem the general problem of uncritical rationalism.

After this Popper dwells more on the specific problem of uncritical rationalism and proposes, as its solution:

“our choice is open. We are free to choose some form of irrationalism, even some radical or comprehensive form. But we are also free to choose a critical form of rationalism, one which frankly admits its limitations, and its basis in an irrational decision…” (Popper 1957, 231)

Now, how about the general problem of uncritical rationalism? What is critical rationalism’s solution to this problem? In Open Society Popper had given no explicit answer. But, the solution of the specific problem of uncritical rationalism is of little (if any) profit, if there is no solution to the general problem of uncritical rationalism. On the other hand, if there was the solution to the general problem of uncritical rationalism, it would contain the solution to the specific problem.

It may be said that the solution of the general problem of uncritical rationalism is there implicitly − in Popper’s acknowleging the problem as pernicious for uncritical rationalism and in his earlier description of rationalism (rational attitude) as “an attitude of readiness to listen to critical arguments and to learn from experience… an attitude of admitting that ‘I may be wrong and you may be right, and by an effort, we may get nearer to the truth’.” (Popper 1957, 225) Yes, but this implicitly present solution was lacking explicit statement. This explicit statement was given by Bartley and accepted by Popper.

It is appropriate to remark that Popper, in Realism and Aims of Science did acknowledge the importance of Bartley’s contribution. Two fragments are especially pertinent to our discussion:

“It was only recently that I began to suspect … that my own approach to the theory of knowledge was more revolutionary… This suspicion arose from a new way of viewing my own approach, and its relation to the problem situation in philosophy; a way that was suggested to me by my friend W.W.Bartley, III.” (Popper 1983, 18)

“It seems to me that Bartley’s simple formulation – that justification can be replaced by non-justificational criticism – and his emphasis on the change of focus involved in the transition from the various justificationist philosophies to a critical philosophy which does not aim at justification is most illuminating… Bartley’s formulation also helps to explain why I can agree with so much that has been said by various irrationalists against rationalism and rationalist attempts to justify our beliefs, though I make no concession to irrationalism, but insist, on the contrary, that any theory or belief may, and should, be made subject to severe and searching rational criticism…” (Popper 1983, 27)

Bold style mine. “I make no concession to irrationalism” can hardly be interpreted otherwise than renouncement of the description of critical rationalism as “minimum concession to irrationalism”. In this prospect, suggested by Bartley, the proper answer to irrationalism is not the “minimum concession” of admitting that rationalist attitude “is based upon an irrational decision”, “an irrational faith in reason”. The proper answer is renouncing the justificationist principle “that any assumption which cannot be supported either by argument or by experience is to be discarded” – replacing it with the principle of openness to criticism. And the difference between critical and uncritical (justificationist) rationalism consists not in “minimum concession to irrationalism”, but in adhering to completely different principles of rationality. Making this clear is principal Bartley’s contribution to critical rationalism.

 

3. Convergence

Diller: Key elements of pancritical rationalism are already present in critical rationalism.”

Rejoinder: Yes. But this is hardly proper criticism of pancritical rationalism because,

on the one side, Bartley did admit that pancritical rationalism is dealing with the problem of limits of rationality “within the general framework of his {Popper’s} own approach” (Bartley 1984, 105); and Bartley did acknowledge that ‘pancritical rationalism’ was suggested to him by Popper’s lecture “On the Sources of Knowledge and of Ignorance” and by Popper’s falsificationism;

on the other side, Popper, under influence of Bartley, has “incorporated” (in Addendum to fourth edition of The Open Society and Its Enemies) “the principle that everything is open to criticism (from which this principle itself is not exempt)” (Popper 1971, 408-409) – the précis of pancritical rationalism, and (in Realism and the Aim of Science) have adopted “a new way of viewing my own approach, and its relation to the problem situation in philosophy; a way that was suggested to me by my friend W.W.Bartley, III.” (Popper 1983, 18)

 

4. “Tossing Yarrow Stalks” and “Irrational Decision”

Next Diller’s criticism of Bartley concerns with Popper’s description of critical rationalism as “form of rationalism … which frankly admits … its basis in an irrational decision” (Popper 1957, 231).

Diller: Bartley sees the need to make such an irrational decision as being a serious liability of critical rationalism. No moral decision is needed to accept pancritical rationalism; Bartley sees nothing wrong in someone deciding to accept pancritical rationalism as a result of some arbitrary method such as "tossing yarrow stalks" (Retreat, second edition, p. 94, fn. 34).

Rejoinder: Let us begin with "tossing yarrow stalks" and look at the fragment in which the phrase occurs. The whole point of this fragment is that what matters for rationality is

not the source of our beliefs (or moral attitudes), what makes us to believe (or accept) them initially,

but our attitude of holding them open to criticism. I think it is right, and is the same thing that Popper says in the lecture “On the Sources of Knowledge and of Ignorance”.

In particular, the sentence in which “yarrow stalks” occurs is:

“…when one is concerned with the question of whether a decision is criticisable, it hardly matters whether that decision was originally made as a result of argument, … or whether he or she decided by tossing yarrow stalks or by some other arbitrary method(Bartley 1984, 94).

As far as I see it, this statement means only that the question of “the sources” of “decision” is quite irrelevant to the question of whether a “decision” is criticisable. Bartley does not say – and, I think, does not mean – that in all other respects there is nothing wrong in making important “decisions”, such as accepting critical or pancritical rationalism, by "tossing yarrow stalks or some other arbitrary method". There is no reason to consider Bartley as a proponent of a crazy epistemology-and-morality in which we accept positions by tossing yarrow stalks and then criticize them with arguments using as premises other positions accepted by the method of tossing yarrow stalks.

So, I think that Diller misinterprets Bartley when he attributes to him the view that there is “nothing wrong in someone deciding to accept pancritical rationalism as a result of some arbitrary method such as "tossing yarrow stalks"”.

 

Now about “irrational decision”-“moral decision”. Bartley did not write that “no moral decision is needed to accept pancritical rationalism”; neither did he write that “the need to make such an irrational decision” is “a serious liability of critical rationalism”. Bartley makes just a minor criticism-correction (in a footnote on p.106) to Popper’s statement that “a rationalist attitude must be first adopted if any argument or experience is to be effective, and it cannot therefore be based upon argument or experience” (Popper 1957, 230). Bartley’s objection is that for a particular argument to be effective, it is not necessary that a person has already accepted a rationalist attitude; much less is nesessary: that this person was open to this particular argument at this particular moment.

This objection, made by Bartley but casually, can be strengthened. It may be argued, that acceptance of rational attitude need not be “irrational decision” – it is really neither irrational, nor decision.

1) It is not irrational. Popper’s admission of necessity of “irrational decision” is based upon argument: "neither logical argument nor experience can establish the rationalist attitude; for only those who are ready to consider argument or experience, and who have therefore adopted this attitude already, will be impressed by them" (Popper 1957, 230). Italicizing mine, − and the phrase italicized is mistaken; it is non sequitur. To see this, we need to clarify the meaning of the vague phrase “to adopt the attitude”. As far as I see it, there are two alternatives.

First, stronger meaning: “to adopt the rationalist attitude” means conscious self-identification with this attitude. If so, then adopting rationalist attitude is not necessary for a person to be impressed by argument or experience. It is not the case that a person must first make conscious self-identification with rationalist attitude, and this enables him/her to be influenced by argument or experience. It is the case that a person is influenced by argument and experience before he/she makes conscious self-identification with rationalist attitude.

Second, weaker meaning: “to adopt the rationalist attitude” means to have a mental disposition of being “ready to consider argument and experience”. But such a mental disposition is not a simple matter of absent/present; it is a matter of degrees. There is no point (moment) of adoption rationalist attitude, in this sense.  All people have it, to some degree. In this sense, all people are rationalists, to some degree (though in some cases this degree may happen to be negligibly small). Starting with some inborn disposition, we develop (or degrade) it throughout our life under influence of experience and arguments, i.e. rationally, in Popper's meaning of "rationality".

2) It is not decision. As far as our beliefs and moral attitudes are concerned, we do not decide – we do make judgments (and, surely, we do not make them by "tossing yarrow stalks"). We decide on our actions – what to do in a particular situation – but not on what to believe or value. We may be persuaded by arguments into believing X or (re)valuing Y, but do not decide that from now or some other moment on we will believe X or value Y.[1]

 

5. How non-justificationism is not to be understood

Diller: “Bartley thinks that a person should abandon a position if the argument which supports that position is shown to be invalid (Retreat, second edition, p. 71). However, only a justificationist should do that…”

Rejoinder: Let us look at what Bartley really writes on the page 71. Despite Diller’s (mis)description, Bartley writes nothing about whether a person should or should not abandon a position if the argument which supports that position is shown to be invalid. Bartley writes quite a different thing: that if a person does not abandon a position if the argument which supports that position is shown to be invalid, this means that the position “far from depending on argument, was held independently of it” (Bartley 1984, 71).

 

Diller: “An anti-justificationist should only abandon a truth-apt position if falsehoods can be derived from it. … Bartley subscribes to the justificationist fallacy I call the strategy of attacking foundations which usually has four stages:

  1. Find a theory you do not like.
  2. Locate its foundations.
  3. Criticise those foundations and show that they are false
  4. Conclude that the entire theory is incorrect or false or radically flawed or intellectually bankrupt.

However, just because a theory follows from false premises does not mean that it itself is false.”

Rejoinder: The first objection against this charge is that it is based on misinterpretation of Bartley’s statements on p. 71 of The Retreat to Commitment, as explained above. The interesting thing about this objection is that by making it I risk to be charged with committing the same “justificationist fallacy” − “the strategy of attacking foundations”. Really, on Diller’s description, it is good and well to charge anyone with anything on whatever ficticious grounds, and if someone shows that there are no real grounds for this charge, he is committing “justificationist fallacy” − “the strategy of attacking foundations”.

So, my second objection is that what Diller calls the strategy of attacking foundations” is not justificationist fallacy, except if it is believed to be the only way to criticize a theory, or if it is believed to be able to prove falsity of the theory criticized.

If “the strategy of attacking foundations” was “the justificationist fallacy”, then Popper would be guilty of it at least as well as Bartley. For Popper often did criticize different theories by “attacking foundations” – for example, in The Open Society and Its Enemies. For example, the great deal of Popper’s criticism of Marxism is not derivation of falsehoods from it, but criticism of arguments of Marx and his followers.

But this is not Popper’s (or Bartley’s) fault – for “the strategy of attacking foundations” is usually good and reasonable (though not universally applicable) strategy.

Suppose a person P believes that a theory T is true because of arguments A, B, C. Now, if you succeed to make such a criticism of A, B, C that P admits that they are unsound, then P has no reason to believe T and will, probably, renounce it. In any case, he would be dishonest to continue to invoke A, B, C as reasons to believe that P is true; he must either find other arguments or admit that he believes T for no reasons at all. Usually, such acknowledgment is pernicious for T (despite the fact that it is not proven that T is false).

Is it “justificationism”? If it is, then both Popper and Bartley were justificationists. But, it is not justificationism in the sense in which Popper and Bartley did use the word.

Popper’s and Bartley’s “anti-justificationism” is not denial that our theories usually need to be supported by some arguments. It is just explanation that such a support does not “justify” anything in the sense of proving it true or highly probable (in the sense of probability calculus). For all supporting arguments use some premises which can not be “justified”, so the whole chain remains “unjustified”. But this does not mean that we need not arguments to support our theories.

We usually do need some arguments to support our theories. It is clear why. It is not the case that we accept theories on whim, for no reasons at all. We usually accept them for some reasons. At least, the reason for accepting a theory is that it seems to us to be a good solution to some explanatory problems. Now, if it is demonstrated that theory does not really solve the problem it was intended to solve, or that there are better solutions, this may be good enough reason to renounce it. And we may have some other arguments which support our acceptance of a theory. If it is demonstrated convincingly (for us) that all arguments which did make us to believe that T is true are mistaken, we will hardly continue to believe that T is true.  It will hardly be reasonable to continue to believe it.

(This does not contradict with acknowledging that it is inevitable to hold some positions without having any arguments to support them, because they just seem true to us. This acknowledgement, together with anti-dogmatic reservation that such unsupported positions may be mistaken and may be criticized and revised, is the core of non-justificationism.)

So, “the strategy of attacking foundations” is usually useful and reasonable strategy. Though it can not prove that a theory under discussion is false, it can provide us with good reasons to disqualify this theory as “radically flawed or intellectually bankrupt”.

To explain it a bit differently, I will refer to Popper’s formulation, in the book In Search of a Better World, of “The principles that form the basis of every rational discussion, that is, of every discussion undertaken in the search for truth…” These principles are: “1. The principle of fallibility… 2. The principle of rational discussion: we want to try, as impersonally as possible, to weigh up our reasons for and against a theory… 3. The principle of approximation to the truth…” (Popper 1992, 199)

Now, if in rational discussion we are “to weigh up our reasons for and against a theory”, then our criticism of a theory may be either providing new arguments (reasons) against the theory, or demolishing some earlier provided arguments (reasons) for the theory. Both “strategies” are equally legitimate and equally apt to influence results of “weighing up”.

 

Literature

Antoni Diller's website. On critical and pancritical rationalism.  http://www.cantab.net/users/antoni.diller/rationalism/pancritical.html

Artigas, M. 1999. The Ethical Nature of Karl Popper’s Theory of Knowledge. Bern, Berlin, Bruxelles, Frankfurt am Main, New York, Wien: Peter Lang.

Bartley, W.W. 1984. The Retreat to Commitment. 2-nd ed. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

Musgrave, A. 2009. "Can I Decide What to Believe?", in A.Musgrave, Secular Sermons.  Otago University Press.

Percival, R. S. 2012. The Myth of Closed Mind. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

Popper, K. 1957. The Open Society and Its Enemies. 3-th ed. London: Routledge, vol.2.

Popper, K. 1963. “On the Sources of Knowledge and of Ignorance”, in K.Popper,  Conjectures and Refutations. London and New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Popper, K. 1971. The Open Society and Its Enemies. 5-th ed. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, vol.2.

Popper, K. 1974. Intellectual Autobiography. In P.A.Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of Karl Popper. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

Popper, K. 1992. In Search of a Better World. London and New York: Routledge.

Popper, K. 1983. Realism and the Aim of Science. London and New York: Routledge.

[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]



[1] I ought an acknowledgement to A.Musgrave and R.S.Percival for earlier explicit statement of this view, with respect to beliefs. Percival also defends the thesis that all people are rational, which I use with a proviso (which seems to me important) “to some degree”.