[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]

[Return to Content]

2. The Soul Theory Against the Brain Theory.

The Knowledge Argument

It is convenient to present the arguments of dualists and materialists (supporters of the soul theory and the brain theory) in the form of a dialogue.

Participants of the dialogue:

Mike – a physiologist who had made many postmortem examinations of human bodies and vivisections of animal bodies and had never seen any such thing as a soul. So he thinks that the soul is old women’s tale.

Helen – a philosopher-dualist who believes that the mind cannot be something physical and that its materialistic explanations (the brain theory) do not stand the criticisms.

Mike: I am sure that there is no such thing as a soul. I and my colleagues made millions of postmortem examinations and vivisections, and no soul was ever found.

Helen: You talk nonsense. The soul is, by the very meaning of the word, nonphysical – such that cannot be seen or touched. No wonder that you have not found it − you could not find it, in principle. You can find only physical things, and whatever you find cannot be a soul.

Mike: I think it is not me but you who is talking nonsense. You talk of something nobody has ever seen or touched, something “in principle” unseeable and undetectable by whatever apparatus possible. However, if so, then there is no reason to believe that it exists, and there “in principle” cannot be any such reasons. Your “soul” is a pure mystification.

Helen: It is not so. There are good reasons to believe that the soul exists, and there is no mysticism in this. We know not only about what can be seen or perceived by other external senses (touch, hearing, scent, and taste) or detected by some physical devices. We know also about these sensations, about our other feelings and emotions (pain, pleasure, grief, happiness, etc.), about our thoughts, beliefs, doubts, and desires – as we subjectively experience them and are subjectively aware of them. Human subjective experiences and thoughts cannot be seen, touched, or detected by physical devices; we know about them not through observations of physical processes but directly by introspection, for it is ourselves who experience and think. The fact that human beings subjectively experience various sensations and emotions and have subjective awareness and thoughts is something beyond the physical facts. Human selves, capable of subjective experiences and awareness, are just as real as physical reality. Such a self (≡ mental subject) is what is usually called “soul”.

Mike: Science has found out that our sensations, emotions, and thoughts are nothing but physical processes in our nervous systems and brains.

Helen: Science has not found out any such thing and could not do this. All that science has found out (and all that it can find out) is that our sensations, emotions, and thoughts are closely connected with the processes in our brains and nervous systems and that some processes in the nervous system can evoke some feelings or some changes in processes of thinking. That is, science has found out that there is a close connection between processes in the brain and the mind. However, your contention is very different: that processes in the brain and states (processes) of the mind are the same thing. Your statement not only does not follow from the statement about a close connection between the mind and the brain but directly contradicts it. If we say that there is a connection between processes in the brain and the mind, this means that the brain and the mind are not the same thing but different things. Vice versa, if we say that the brain and the mind is the same thing, then it is wrong to talk about a connection between them. A statement about a connection between A and B makes sense only if A is not B. It is wrong to say that A is connected with B (or that A causes B) if A is B.

Mike: OK. I renounce the statement that our feelings and thoughts are connected with processes in our brains. I think that our feelings and thoughts are processes in our brains.

Helen: This is your personal opinion, not a scientifically proven fact,  and there are weighty arguments against it.

To begin with, physical processes in the brain and states and processes of the mind have no common properties except approximate simultaneity; therefore, they cannot be the same thing. The processes in my brain are movements, changes of forms, compressions and expansions of some physical bodies. It is something that we can (in principle, by means of some device) scan and see. However, we cannot scan and see feelings and thoughts as such, for they are felt and thinkable, not seen.

I never saw processes in my brain, but I always know what are my feelings and thoughts are. Therefore, my feelings and thoughts are not something that may be seen or touched; they are present directly in my consciousness as something without physical properties.

Mike: I think that this argument is mistaken. It is the same as to say: I know about colours, sounds, heat, and so on, although I never observed electromagnetic waves and sound fluctuations of air and did not measure kinetic energy and so on. Therefore, colours, sounds, heat, and so on are not and cannot be electromagnetic waves, air fluctuations, kinetic energy, and so on.

However, we all know (science tells us) that in fact colours are properties to reflect electromagnetic waves of certain frequencies, sounds are air fluctuations, heat is kinetic energy, and so on. In the same way, feelings and thoughts are certain states of the brain, and it is probable that science will once discover that pain is such and such a physical state (structure) of the brain, pleasure is such and such another physical state (structure) of the brain, and so on.

Helen: Your objection does not take into account the important distinction (made in the XVII century by Descartes and Lock) between primary properties, which belong to things as they really are, and secondary properties, which belong to human subjective perception of things (or of their primary properties). This distinction explains how heat can be kinetic energy, colour – electromagnetic waves, and so on. The explanation is very simple: electromagnetic waves of certain frequencies are felt by a person as certain feelings-of-colours, kinetic energy is felt by a person as thermal feelings (how-it-feels when it is cold or warm or hot), and so on. However, this explanation already assumes the existence of the mind as a realm of subjectivity − the existence of the mental subject (self) who possesses the ability to feel (not in the sense of a behavioural reaction but in the sense of subjective experiencing – how-it-feels). No sensations of colours, thermal sensations, and so on would exist without subjectivity, that is, without the mind (or the mental subject-self), although frequencies of electromagnetic waves and values of kinetic energy would be just the same.

Thus, given 1) physical bodies and processes with their primary properties and 2) the perceiving mind (self), we can easily explain 3) the existence of thermal, visual, auditory, and other sensations. However, given only the physical processes, it is impossible to explain the existence of the perceiving mind (self), and therefore, it is impossible to explain thermal, visual, auditory, and other sensations.

Thus, the example with colours, sounds, heat, and so on not only does not disprove the dualism of the mind and physical reality – it serves as an illustration or manifestation of this dualism.

Mike: However, is not the mind (self) itself just a secondary property that is derivative from primary, physical properties?

Helen: No, it is not. All secondary properties presuppose the existence of the mind – they exist only in relation to the mind. Therefore, the mind itself is not a secondary property.

All secondary properties are relations between two fundamental realities – the physical world and the mind (self). The mind and the physical world are two “sides” of the relation of external-sensual perception – a subject and an object. Because all secondary properties exist as if “on the joint” of these “sides”, each of the “sides” is not a secondary property.

Thus, the mind (self), as well as the physical world, is not a secondary property; it is one of the two fundamental realities that make the existence of all secondary properties possible.

Mike: However, if we achieve the exact scientific knowledge of the correspondence between processes in the brain and sensations, feelings, desires, and thoughts?

Helen: It would only confirm that the mind is one thing, whereas the physical processes in the brain are another. It is because to get such knowledge, we would need information, on the one hand, about the mental states (sensations, emotions, desires, and thoughts) of a person and, on the other hand, about the physical processes that occur in the brain of this person when he has these mental states. To establish the correspondence, we need information about the mental states of a person to begin with, and we cannot get such information through observations of the processes in his brain – we can get it only by asking the person what he feels, wants, and thinks. So, the two sides between which we are trying to establish correspondence must be really two sides – two different “things”, not one and the same thing.

 

The Knowledge Argument

One of the most interesting arguments against materialism is called the knowledge argument. It was advanced in different forms by Thomas Nagel and Frank Jackson.

The argument points out that different subjective experiences have a specific qualitative character – how-it-feels (how it feels when it pains, or when you are sad, etc.; what the feeling of pain, sadness, etc. is like as a feeling), and that this specific qualitative character how-it-feels cannot be captured by whatever physical (or behavioural, etc.) descriptions. It is possible to know all about the physical facts (processes in the brain) associated with a certain feeling, without knowing anything about the feeling itself – what it is like, how it feels. Therefore, the feeling is something nonphysical.

There is something such as how it feels for someone when he is hurt, sad, etc. This how-it-feels is a specific nonphysical fact. Such facts are so peculiar that they cannot be communicated in language: it is impossible to explain to a person who has never had some feeling (or some similar feeling), what this feeling is like (how it feels). No amount of information about physical processes in the brain will help. For example, if a person was from birth deprived of all olfactory sensations, it is impossible to explain to him how this or that smell feels; no knowledge about physical processes in the nervous system and the brain (responsible for this sensation) will help.

Another example is from Thomas Nagel’s classical article “What is it like to be a bat?” Most species of bats have no vision; some species have weak vision. Bats make their orientation in space mostly by means of a very complex echolocation system. It seems probable (if we don’t think, as Descartes did, that only human beings have minds, whereas all animals are just complicated machines that subjectively feel nothing) that bats have specific subjective feelings-experiences of echolocational perception; but it is impossible for us, human beings, to know how it feels (what it is like to be a bat). It is possible that the bat’s echolocational perceptions feel like our visual perceptions. (However, if so, then how does it feel for those species of bats which have both – visual and echolocational – perceptions?) It is just as well possible that they are quite unlike any human subjective experiences; in this case, we are quite incapable of imagining how it feels (what it is like to be a bat). We could have whatever detailed, exact, exhaustive knowledge of all physical processes involved in this perception; we could understand perfectly how the echolocational system of a bat “works” at the level of physical processes of the brain; however, all this knowledge would give us no idea of how it feels subjectively (what it is like to be a bat). Nevertheless, it feels somehow. There is something such as how it feels, what it is like to be a bat – and this something is outside the realm of physical facts.

Likewise, bats, if they had powerful intellect and highly developed science, could learn everything about the physical facts having to do with visual perception; nevertheless, they cannot know how it feels – to have visual perceptions. S. Law, following T. Nagel, proposes to imagine aliens from some far-off planet who have no sight, but have instead – as bats – echolocational perception. These aliens are very clever; their science is much more advanced than ours. If they arrive on Earth and research human visual perception, they can find out all physical facts that are associated with it. They can know about all processes in the brain of a person who sees a red flower or a blue sky. However, they will not be able to acquire any knowledge of what it is like (how it feels) – to see a red flower or a blue sky; what it is like to be a being with visual perception.[1]

The most well-known and influential version-explanation of the knowledge argument is the thought experiment of Mary’s black-and-white world, devised by the Australian philosopher Frank Jackson.[2] Let us imagine a woman by the name of Mary, who from birth lived in a room with special illumination that makes all colours look as shades of grey (ranging from black to white). She never got outside the room and never experienced sensations of such colours as red, blue, green, etc. Mary became an outstanding scientist who specializes on colour perception. She knew all the physical facts about perceptions of green, red, blue, and other colours: the frequencies of the waves of light, the physical processes in the nervous system, the brain, etc. One wonderful day, she left her room and got into the world with normal illumination. Mary was struck: now she knew what it is like – to have the sensations of red, green, blue, and other colours; what these sensations are like. She did not know it before, despite the fact that she knew all the physical facts about colours and their perceptions.

Mary has learned something new, some new facts: how it feels – to see the red, green, blue, and other colours. However, even before this, Mary knew all the physical facts that have to do with colour perceptions. Therefore, those new facts that Mary has learned are not physical facts. This means that besides physical facts (facts about physical reality), there are also other facts – facts about the specific character of various subjective experiences, about the mind as a personal world of human subjectivity. Therefore, physical reality is not the entire reality. Entire reality includes, besides physical reality, minds. The mind is something nonphysical (non-material).

 

The impossibility of acquiring knowledge about the character of subjective experiences that essentially differ from our own is a direct consequence of the fact that the mind of every person is a personal, private “world” with exclusive access (only this person has direct access to it). In this respect, the mind cardinally differs from the physical world, which is common, public, and equally accessible to all minds. Even about other people, we can only guess that their experiences are similar to our own corresponding experiences, but we cannot check whether this guess is true. It is possible that you subjectively experience red colour (the colour of blood) as I experience green (the colour of grass), and that you experience green as I experience red. It is as well possible that your subjective experiences of colours are unlike any of my subjective experiences. The possibility of communication and understanding between people testifies that different people have a common structure of relations between different sensations and between the sensations and their causal sources. For example, for different people, the sensation of the colour of grass (1) is stable, (2) is similar to the colour sensations evoked by other things that are called green, and (3) is not similar to the colour sensations evoked by things that are called blue or red. However, the qualitative subjective character of every sensation may be, in principle, unique for each person. Noone can get into the mind of another person and experience how it really is for him to experience the colour of grass, etc.

 

The knowledge argument can be formulated as follows. However full our knowledge of physical processes in the brain is, it tells nothing about what the corresponding subjective feelings-experiences are like – how they feel, are experienced subjectively. The facts that they feel in a certain way (and not somehow otherwise) are special facts that are beyond the realm of physical facts. That is, everything that belongs to the mind as a personal realm of subjective experiences and awareness (how it is experienced subjectively – to have this sensation or emotion, to be aware of some fact, to understand some statement, to wish this or that) is outside the realm of the physical, matter. The facts about the mind are nonphysical facts – facts about nonphysical reality. Therefore, the mind as a personal realm of subjectivity is a nonphysical reality.

In further details, this argument is discussed below in the form of a dialogue.

Helen: I propose to discuss one of the most influential arguments against materialism.

Imagine that somewhere far away there is a planet Zet populated with intelligent beings – let us call them zetians. Their perceptions are a bit different from ours. They do not have perceptions of some kind that we have; perhaps, they have instead perceptions of some other kind that we do not have, or compensate the lacking perceptions with much higher sensitivity of other perceptions. Though the perceptions of zetians differ from ours, they allow to obtain the same (or even more precise) physical information (about location, size, form, mass, temperature, etc.) as obtainable by human beings. For example, zetians are deaf, but can very well communicate by means of a highly developed gesture language and of writing; or they are blind, but have instead, like bats, advanced echolocational perception; or they have sight, but do not distinguish colours, see all colours as shades of grey... Let us settle on such a version: zetians do not have olfactory sensations.

Zetians are very clever, and their science is much more developed than ours. They have equipment that allows to scan any processes in a human body, and to get any knowledge about the physical structures of a human body and about physical processes in it.

Suppose that zetians have arrived on Earth. They have learned human language and heard that human beings feel smells. Zetians want to find out how it feels – for example, to smell the scent of a rose. By means of their equipment, zetians can obtain any physical information about processes in the body (brain) of a person who smells a rose. But can they learn in this way how the aroma of a rose smells (feels)?

Mike: No, they cannot.

Helen: But how can it be so? On the one hand, zetians can obtain any knowledge about any physical properties and processes. On the other hand, on having obtained all physical information they want, they still cannot know how a rose smells, how its aroma feels. The conclusion follows that the sensation of the smell of a rose (as well as any other mental state) is not physical properties and processes.

Mike: But zetians do not even exist, we have just imagined them!

Helen: This does not matter. What does matter is that if they existed, then all physical information having to do with smells and their perception by human beings would not enable zetians to find out what olfactory sensations are like.

If you do not like zetians, you can imagine a colour-blind physicist who knows everything about the physical structures and processes of the human nervous-brain system that are responsible for colour perceptions, but does not know what the sensation of red or green is like.

Or you can imagine a woman by the name of Mary. From birth, she wears on her eyes, never removing, a contact film that makes her visual perception black-and-white. (Let us imagine that it is a special organic contact film that grows together with her eyes. May be, Mary knows nothing about this and thinks of herself as an ordinary colour-blind person, but actually some scientists carry out an experiment on her to test an organic monochromatic film). Mary became a neurophysicist who specializes exactly on the physical structures and processes of the human nervous-brain system that are responsible for the perception of colours. She knows everything about these structures and processes. However, she does not know what the sensation of red or green is like (how it looks for human beings, how it feels subjectively), and she cannot know it unless she removes the contact film.

Mike: But would she really acquire new knowledge, if she removes the film? Mary knows that people have various colour sensations, she only “does not know” what they are like (how they feel). If she removes the film, she would not be able to report any new fact about colour perceptions, so she would not acquire any new knowledge. Surely, in some other sense, she “learns” something new, viz., what it is like to feel red or green. However, I think that really it is not knowledge – it is a new experience, which, from the point of view of materialism, is just some specific physical state of her brain.

Helen: I can propose two objections.

First, it is not the case that Mary has merely acquired a new experience. She did not know before, and she knows now what people mean when they talk of seeing green (the colour of grass) or blue (the colour of sky) colour. Surely, they are talking not about the frequencies of electromagnetic waves (the vast majority of people know nothing of them) and not about physical processes in the brain (which they do not observe).

Now Mary will be able to identify the visual sensations or red, blue, green, etc. when she has them again; so she now knows what they are like, how they feel.

We can modify the thought experiment with Mary. Imagine that the contact film is not black-and-white, but changes colours every day so that every day of week has its own colour. On Monday everything looks black-grey-white, on Tuesday – lighter or darker red, on Wednesday – blue, on Thursday – green, etc. Mary feels these differences and calls them “monday sensation”, “tuesday sensation”, etc. However, she does not know that this is how other people feel various colours, what they mean when they talk of sensations of red, or blue, or green. Scientists who carry out the experiment do not tell her about this; she has no means to investigate her own brain (to compare its states with the brain states of other people when they have perceptions of colours); there is no correlation between these her sensations and colour-relevant descriptions by other people: people say that the grass is green, the sky is blue, a rose is red, but for Mary, all the difference between the colours of grass, sky, rose, etc. is that some things are darker and others lighter. She regards those changes of visual sensation that happen with her every day as a strange feature of her own mind, and does not guess that they have anything to do with what other people call colours. She has experiences of colour sensations[3], but she does not know what the sensations of red, blue, green, etc. are like – what it is like (how it feels) for other people to see the earth as black, a rose as red, the sky as blue, grass as green, etc., what do they mean when they say that the earth is black, a rose is red, the sky is blue, grass is green, etc. Now, let us imagine that one happy day some chemical got into Mary’s eyes and destroyed the film without causing any injury to her eyes. Mary looks around and exclaims with amazement: “What a miracle! Today is Friday, but the earth has suddenly became monday, a rose – tuesday, the sky – wednesday, and grass – thursday?!” Suddenly, a guess dawned on Mary: So that is what the sensations of black, red, blue, green, etc. are like!!!

It seems that Mary has learned something new after all, viz., what the sensations of green, red, etc. are like, how they feel. Before this, she knew only about electromagnetic waves and brain states associated with these sensations, and now she knows about the sensations how-they-feel. She happened to have read in books on neurophysics that the sensation of red is such-and-such brain structure. However, the brain structure is one thing, whereas how-it-feels is another. A sensation is how-it-feels.

Mary knew what physical processes occur in the brain of a person when he has the sensation of red or blue. Nevertheless, she did not know what those sensations are like (how they feel subjectively) that people experience when there are corresponding physical processes in their brains. In particular, she did not know that when the physical processes that are described in some books on neurophysics as the sensation of red occur in the brain of a person, the person’s subjective experience is like her tuesday sensations, and likewise with all other colour sensations. It turns out, that the specific qualities of various subjective experiences of colour vision are real facts about the world (about minds, which are parts of the world), and these facts are not contained in the whole set of all physical facts. All physical facts having to do with colour sensations are equally compatible with any of the possibilities: the sensation (subjective experience) of red could happen to be like Mary's monday sensation, or tuesday sensation, or saturday sensation, or unlike any sensation (subjective experience) she ever had (as in the initial version of the story about Mary – with a black-and-white film). That the sensation (subjective experience) of red happened to be such as it is, not of some other quality, is the fact that does not belong to the set of all physical facts, for in the light of all physical facts, the sensation (subjective experience) of red could happen to be any.

 

The second objection is that it does not matter whether Mary has obtained some new knowledge or just had some new experiences. What does matter is the fact that these experiences have a specific subjective (phenomenal) character that cannot be captured by whatever physical description. I hope you will not deny that there is something what it is like to see a red-coloured thing or to feel pain? Would you deny that it feels somehow, that every such sensation has a specific subjective (phenomenal) character?

Mike: No, I will not.

Helen: Then you must admit that there are facts of how-it-feels and that they are beyond the realm of physical facts. That is, they are nonphysical facts – facts about something nonphysical.

Mike: For a while, I do not see how to repel these arguments, but I still suspect that something is wrong with them. Let us try to approach the problem from another side.

Let us suppose that zetians have found out what processes occur in the nervous-brain system when people, on their own evidences, feel pain and other sensations. Now suppose we ask a zetian: What is the sensation of pain? The zetian can answer: The sensation of pain is such-and-such processes in the nervous-brain system. She can also describe also the differences between these processes and the processes that correspond to other sensations.

Suppose we ask the same question to an ordinary human person. I expect that it would be difficult for him to answer. Probably, the most that he can say is that pain is one of the sensations he sometimes feels, and that it is an unpleasant sensation; however, he will hardly be able to explain clearly what a sensation is and how exactly the sensation of pain differs from other feelings.

If we compare these two answers, we see that the answer of the zetian is more concrete, definite, detailed, and informative. Are not we to draw a conclusion that the zetian, not the ordinary human person, is the one who knows what feelings really are?

Helen: The argument is interesting but, in my opinion, mistaken. One may give to any question a concrete, definite, detailed, and informative answer that is wrong. On the other hand, a less concrete, definite, detailed, and informative answer may be right.

We, human beings, know what pain, grief, or pleasure is, because we have these experiences. When someone says “I feel sad” or “I am happy”, we understand the sense of it, although we cannot explain it to someone who has never experienced sadness or happiness. The feelings of pain, grief, and pleasure are basic experiences that are not reducible to anything else; that is why it is impossible to explain what the feeling of pain, grief, or pleasure is (what it is like) to someone who has never felt them.

We all know what such words as “pain”, “sadness”, “pleasure”, “happiness”, etc. mean. To know this, one need not be a scientist. They are not scientific terms, but concepts of ordinary language, such that everyone understands their meaning. The meaning of these words is what they mean for an ordinary person. Of course, a scientist-physicist or a zetian can use the same words in some other (in particular, physical) sense, but this will not be those pain, sadness, pleasure, happiness that each of us sometimes feels.

When we feel sadness, we know what we feel, although we know nothing about the relevant physical structures and processes in our nervous-brain systems. Vice versa holds as well: If we observe the physical structures and processes of the nervous-brain system of a person through some scanning device, this would tell us nothing about what he feels.

Of course, we could learn these things – in the first case about physical processes, in the second – about feelings, – if we had a table of correspondences between the former and the latter. However, such a table cannot be compiled on the basis of physical information alone – it can be compiled only by comparing physical information with evidences of a person about his feelings.[4]

Thus, we can know everything about what a person feels while knowing nothing about the physical structures and processes of his nervous-brain system, and vice versa, we can know everything about the physical structures and processes of a person’s nervous-brain system while knowing nothing about his feelings.

From this, it logically follows that subjective experiences (sensations, emotions, etc.) are not physical structures and processes of the nervous-brain system. For the same reasons, we should draw a conclusion that they are not any physical entities and processes whatsoever; they are not reducible to the physical.

Variation. When a person says “I feel pain” or “I feel pleasure”, he tells nothing about the spatial locations, sizes, forms, movements of some physical bodies, that is, he tells nothing about physical bodies, structures, properties, and processes – communicates no physical information.[5] Nevertheless, he tells about something! Viz., he tells about sensations and emotions. Hence, sensations and emotions are not physical bodies, structures, properties, and processes.

 

Preliminary Summary

Materialism is based on the view that it is reasonable to believe in the existence of only those things that can be seen, palpated, or registered by some physical device – only what can be observed (directly or indirectly) externally or what, on the assumption of its existence, allows to successfully explain and predict externally observable phenomena according to the laws of nature. Dualism, instead, appeals to the knowledge of a person about his own subjective experiences that cannot be observed from the outside but about which everyone knows.

It is a widespread (in particular, among materialists) belief that science has found out that sensations, emotions, and thoughts are certain physical processes in the nervous system and the brain. However, this belief is mistaken: all the facts and observations to which its supporters can refer are compatible both with the materialistic point of view and with the point of view of dualism, according to which sensations, emotions, and thoughts are subjective experiences of a person that may be caused or conditioned by physical processes in the nervous system and the brain but are not these processes.

We should beware of the mistake that is usual for materialists – the substitutions of the meanings of mental concepts, such as “feeling”, “pain”, etc. Proceeding from materialistic interpretations of scientific theories, their supporters often use mental concepts to mean certain physical processes in the nervous system and the brain or certain behavioural dispositions or functional roles for an organism. However, by doing this, they merely substitute the ordinary meaning of these concepts (as they are commonly understood) with another, very different meaning. It is the same as if I call a cat “dog” and, on this ground, contend that dogs meow. In discussions about the nature of sensations, we need to put aside for a while all anatomic theories about them and address our own experience, experience of every person – for example, the experience designated by the word “pain”. We all know from personal experience, not from anatomic theories, what it means to feel pain. Most people are not familiar with anatomic theories; they know nothing or nearly nothing about structures and processes in the human body (brain) that are responsible for the feeling of pain, but they all know very well what it means to feel pain, what the feel³ng of pain is like. Modern scientists-anatomists know about this exactly as much as a person who lived several thousands years ago when anatomy did not exist yet. (Moreover, because many modern scientists-anatomists confuse the meaning of the word “pain” with the content of some anatomic theories about pain, in this regard, a person who lived several thousands years ago when anatomy did not exist yet has a considerable advantage.) Pain is how it feels when it pains (me or you), neither more nor less. It is a specific (your or mine) subjective experience. The same goes for any other sensation or emotion.

The knowledge argument shows that sensations and emotions cannot be identified with physical processes in the nervous system and the brain of a person: it is possible to know everything about the brain’s physical processes responsible for a certain feeling but to know nothing about the feeling itself, how it feels subjectively.

From within the knowledge of the physical, it is impossible to obtain any knowledge of subjective experiences; and from within the knowledge of subjective experiences, it is impossible to obtain any knowledge of the physical. Any possible knowledge (information, statements) about the physical, by itself (if there is no additional mediating knowledge), does not tell anything at all about subjective experiences of a person. And any possible knowledge (information, statements) about subjective experiences of a person, by itself (if there is no additional mediating knowledge), does not tell anything at all about physical objects and processes.[6]

Therefore, subjective experiences are not physical objects and processes.

 

The aforesaid can be illustrated with the following scheme:

From the point of view of materialism, the human mind and its subject (the self) are identified with the body (the brain), which is part of physical reality. This must mean that all properties and states of the mind, that is, all subjective experiences, are knowable “from within” the knowledge about physical processes; no additional knowledge connecting subjective experiences with physical processes in the body is needed. (Moreover, such additional knowledge is impossible: if all reality is physical reality, then there cannot be any other knowledge besides the knowledge about physical reality.) However, the fact is that “from within” the knowledge about physical processes, without additional connecting knowledge, it is impossible to get any knowledge about subjective experiences. Subjective experiences cannot be seen or detected in some other way within the physical horizon.

From the point of view of dualism, the human mind (the self) is something distinct from (although dependent on) the body and its specific subsystem, the brain, as well as from the whole physical reality. That is why knowledge about subjective experiences is unobtainable from the knowledge about physical processes. We know about them directly through self-consciousness; this direct knowledge is internal for our minds and external to physical reality. We can also know about subjective experiences of other people: either by their testimonies (based on their direct-introspective knowledge of their own mental states) or indirectly – by observations of a person’s body complemented with the mediating knowledge that connects appearances and movements of the human body with subjective experiences. Likewise, scientists would be able to know about the mental states of a person on the basis of knowledge about his brain states complemented with the mediating knowledge of what mental states correspond to various brain states. Thus, on the above scheme, the arrow between the self and the body (the brain) has a double meaning: in the ontological respect, it symbolizes the interaction between the self and the body; in the cognitive respect, it symbolizes the additional mediating knowledge about the correspondences (that result from the interaction) between mental and brain states.

 

The Mind and H2O

Mike: May be, the situation with the mind and the brain is of the same kind as the situation with water and an aggregate of H2O molecules? People always knew about water, although they only recently have learnt about H2O molecules. Thus, “water” surely does not mean “an aggregate of H2O molecules”; nevertheless, water is an aggregate of H2O molecules. We may even say that it is possible to know everything about water (its macroproperties) while knowing nothing about H2O molecules, and it is possible to know everything about H2O molecules while knowing nothing about water.

Helen: It is not so. The situations are entirely different. In the case of water, we have certain stuff, and we know that it is divisible. It is possible to separate very small parts of water, and it is natural to suppose that these parts, probably, are divisible on even smaller ones. That is, our macrolevel knowledge about water already tells us that it is an aggregate of tiny particles. The statement that water is an aggregate of H2O molecules merely specifies this knowledge. On the other hand, if we knew everything about some concrete aggregate of H2O (for example, the one in the glass over there) – all physical properties of these molecules, their quantity and locations, the laws of their interactions, – then all physical macroproperties of the water in the glass are deducible by logical-mathematical means from that information. (Of course, we cannot obtain in this way the knowledge of “secondary” macroproperties of water, such as taste or smell, because they are not physical but mind-relational properties – properties to influence a human mind in a certain way, to evoke certain sensations in it.)

An aggregate of H2O molecules is water under a microscope. Do try to take any feeling how it feels and scrutinize it through a microscope. If you succeed, do not forget to invite me to look at this wonder. J

The Queer Logics of Hofstadter & Dennett

In the collection The Mind’s I, under the edition of and with comments by D. Hofstadter and D. Dennett, the editors write:

“One broad highway leading to dualism goes through the following (bad) argument:

Some facts are not about the properties, circumstances, and relations of physical objects.

Therefore, some facts are about the properties, circumstances, and relations of nonphysical objects.”[7]

I wonder why the argument is “bad”. Where is it mistaken? Do Hofstadter & Dennett deny the premise (that “some facts are not about … physical objects”)? No. In the following discussion, they accept this premise. Do they deny the validity of the argument (that the conclusion follows logically from the premise)? They do not discuss the validity at all. Why? Probably because they find nothing to say against it.

Indeed, if the premise is true, and if we take into account that all facts are facts about something, then the conclusion is tautologically true – like the statement that all unmarried men are not married!

Any fact is a fact about something.

Something may be either physical or not, that is, either physical or nonphysical.

Therefore, any fact is either a fact about something physical or a fact about something nonphysical.

Therefore, if a fact is not about something physical, it is about something nonphysical.

However, let us consider the explanation by Hofstadter & Dennett:

“What’s wrong with this argument? Try to think of examples of facts that are not about physical objects. The fact that the narrator in Moby Dick is called Ishmael is a fact in good standing, but what is it about? One might want to insist (implausibly) that it is really about certain ink shapes on certain bound stacks of printed pages; or one might say (somewhat mysteriously) that it is a fact all right, but it is not about anything at all; or, waving one’s hands a bit, one might say that it is a fact about an abstract object, – in much the way the fact that 641 is a prime number is a fact about an abstract object. But almost no one (we suppose) is attracted to the view that it is a fact about a perfectly real but nonphysical person named Ishmael.”[8]

Of course, it is not. However, this does not indicate the “badness” of the argument at issue at all.

The argument tells nothing about nonphysical persons; it tells about nonphysical objects. If applied to the case of Moby Dick, it follows from the argument that the fact that the narrator in Moby Dick is called Ishmael is a fact about (a) nonphysical object(s). Actually, this conclusion is true.

The fact about the narrator in Moby Dick is a fact about the semantic contents of the book Moby Dick. It is a fact about the novel Moby Dick – that it is said in the novel that the name of the narrator is Ishmael. This semantic content (aboutness) is nonphysical. (In more details, see Section 5 and subsection “The Theory of Three Worlds” of Section 12, Book 2.)

The fact about the narrator in Moby Dick is a fact not about the book as a physical object (about physical properties of the book) but about something nonphysical – about the semantic content that this physical object symbolically represents for the consciousness of a reader. The bound sheets of paper with black marks by themselves, as physical objects, have no meaningful content; they are not “about something”. They have a meaningful content – are “about something” – only insofar as the writer “encoded” into them a certain meaning, which he created in his mind, and other people (readers) are capable to “decode”-understand it – to recreate it in their consciousness.

Incidentally, “a fact about an abstract object … that 641 is a prime number” is also a fact about something nonphysical, namely, about an abstract object, the number 641.

My Friend John and the Masked Man

Mike: I have just read Stephen Law’s interesting philosophical story “The Consciousness Conundrum”[9], in which the knowledge argument is discussed. The author suggests that the argument involves “the masked man fallacy”. I propose to discuss it.

Let us imagine the following situation. I have a friend; his name is John. Yesterday, I heard in TV-news that a masked man has robbed the Delta Bank. It seems that these two facts are quite unconnected with one another. However, it may turn out that the masked man is John, although I do not know this.

Now let us consider the following inference:

My knowledge about John does not contain any knowledge about the masked man. Therefore, John is not the masked man.

This inference is obviously invalid. From the fact that I do not know that John has robbed the bank, it does not logically follow that he has not robbed the bank.

The knowledge argument looks very similar:

The knowledge of physical processes does not contain any knowledge about experiences how they feel. (And vice versa: The knowledge about experiences does not contain any knowledge about physical processes.) Therefore, experiences are not physical processes.

Does this argument not involve the same “masked man fallacy”?

Helen: I think that it does not. These two inferences look similar only on the surface. There is a very essential difference between them that makes the first inference (with the conclusion that John has not robbed the bank) invalid, whereas the second (with the conclusion that the mind is nonphysical) is valid.

In the first case, we have some knowledge about John and some knowledge about the masked man, and it happens that the first does not contain the second. From this, indeed, no conclusion logically follows as to whether John is the masked man or not.

In the second case, the situation is very different. Here, we are talking not about merely some knowledge about physical processes in the nervous-brain system, but about all such knowledge. The contention is that even if we knew everything about physical processes in the nervous-brain system, or even in the whole world, this knowledge would not contain knowledge about experiences how they feel.

If I could know everything about John, and if John really is the masked person who has robbed the bank, the full knowledge about John would contain the knowledge about the masked person who has robbed the bank. For example, if I had a video on which John’s whole life is recorded, then I could see on the video the masked man robbing the bank. Vice versa holds as well: If all possible knowledge about John does not contain knowledge about the masked man who has robbed the bank (for example, if the video records of John’s whole life contain nothing about the robbery of the bank), then it logically follows that John is not the masked man who has robbed the bank.

Mary knew all physical facts about colours and colour sensations. However, whatever all these facts were, the sensation of red could happen to be any. Having learnt what the sensation of red is like (how it feels), Mary has learnt a new fact that is not contained in the whole set of all physical facts having to do with colours and colour sensations. Therefore, facts about sensations are not physical facts.

 

******

Stephen Law writes that it seems to him that the knowledge argument involves “the masked man fallacy”; however, he does not substantiate and does not explain this view, leaving it for readers to think through.

S. Law’s suggestions about “the masked man fallacy” are similar to the objections by Paul Churchland against “the argument from introspection” (see the following subsection). Perhaps, S. Law thinks that the knowledge argument is analogous to the argument from introspection. I think that if there is some analogy between these arguments, it is rather superficial and does not undermine the validity of the knowledge argument. The knowledge argument is closer to the argument that can be obtained by “turning from head on feet” the argument from introspection – to the argument from the impossibility of “extraspection”. The most influential (although, in my opinion, unsatisfactory) objection against this argument and the knowledge argument is given by the materialistic theory of representationism.

The Argument from the Impossibility of "Extraspection" of Mental States

One of the leading modern philosophers-materialists, Paul Churchland, discusses and refutes an argument against materialism that he calls “the argument from introspection”. Churchland formulates it as follows:

“1. My mental states are introspectively known by me as states of my conscious self.

2.   My brain states are not introspectively known by me as states of my conscious self.

Therefore, …

3.   My mental states are not identical with my brain states.”[10]

In such a form, the argument from introspection turns out to be invalid. Churchland compares it with such a reasoning:

“1. Muhammad Ali is widely known as a heavyweight champion.

2.   Cassius Clay is not widely known as a heavyweight champion.

Therefore, …

3.   Muhammad Ali is not identical with Cassius Clay.”[11]

However, actually, “Muhammad Ali” is the sports pseudo of the person named “Cassius Clay”.

After this, Churchland considers another possible version of “the argument from introspection”, which says not that we know by introspection but that it is possible to know by introspection:

“1. My mental states are knowable by introspection.

2.      My brain states are not knowable by introspection.

Therefore, …

3. My mental states are not identical with my brain states.”[12]

Churchland objects that a materialist can decline this argument by denying its premise (2.). Instead, he can contend that we introspectively know about brain states, although we receive this information under “mentalistic descriptions”:

“…if mental states are indeed brain states, then it is really brain states we have been introspecting all along, though without fully appreciating what they are. And if we can learn to think of and recognize those states under mentalistic descriptions, … then we can certainly learn to think of and recognize them under their more penetrating neurophysiological descriptions.”[13]

On Churchland’s view, the situation is the same as in the case of water: we can know as much as we want about its macroproperties without knowing that water is an aggregate of H2O molecules.

Is Churchland right? I think that he is not. To understand this better, let us make a generalized description of the situations similar to the situation with water and H2O.

I mean the following. There is something about which we can know, so to say, at two levels – superficial (water) and deeper (H2O). To each of these levels of knowledge, its own form of description corresponds. Because at the superficial level we obtain more general, undetailed information, this information does not comprise the detailed information obtainable at the deeper level. That is why we can know as much as we want about macroproperties of water without knowing about its microstructure (that it consists of H2O molecules). That is, the deeper is not reducible to the superficial; the detailed is not reducible to the general. However, the superficial is reducible to the deeper, and the general is reducible to the detailed – is contained in it. If we have full enough detailed information about a thing (at the deeper level), it already contains all more general information about the thing (at the superficial level). If we know much enough about H2O molecules, from this information, it is possible to obtain any knowledge about macroproperties of water.

The situation in the case of mental states and brain states (neurophysiological states) is entirely different. If the only difficulty were that the neurophysiological description of the states and processes of the brain is unobtainable from our introspective knowledge of mental states (is obtainable only by external observation via complex equipment), it would not be a serious problem for materialism. However, the real difficulty is different – it is that the knowledge that we obtain introspectively is unobtainable by whatever external observations – neither directly nor via whatever equipment.

For example, from the observations of neurostructures and processes in a brain (if they are not supplemented by some introspectively obtained information), it is impossible to know that when certain processes occur, it is felt as pain (it hurts), and that when certain other processes occur, it feels pleasurable or cheerful. Or let us imagine a person who sees or imagines a tree or a rose; we do not know about this, but we can observe through special devices any neurostructures and processes in his brain. Whatever we observe, we cannot know from it what he sees or imagines. The same goes for thoughts: from observations of neurostructures and processes in the brain of a person who thinks about something, it is impossible to know what he thinks about and what he thinks about it. (Surely, all this is impossible provided that we have no additional knowledge that connects the processes in the brain with mental states and that cannot be obtained by observations of the processes in the brain, without introspective evidence about mental states.) All physical information about neurostructures and processes in the brain (that is obtainable by external observations) does not contain any information about feelings, emotions, the contents of imagination, thoughts, etc. That is, all physical information does not contain any information about mental states.

Thus, instead of the argument from introspection, we can formulate the argument from the impossibility of “extraspection” (external observation) of mental states:

(1)  Brain states (states of a brain as a material, physical system) are entirely knowable by external observation without introspection.

(2) Mental states are not knowable by external observation without introspection.

Therefore,

(3) Mental states are not brain states (states of a brain as a material, physical system).

We can draw an analogy with Muhammad Ali – Cassius Clay. Let us suppose that we can know from some source (for example, from his biography) everything about a person by name Classius Cai but cannot know from this source anything about Alimmad Muhi. From this, it logically follows that Alimmad Muhi is not Classius Cai.

(1) It is possible to know everything about Classius Cai from the biography.

(2) It is impossible to know anything about Alimmad Muhi from the biography.

Therefore,

(3) Alimmad Muhi is not Classius Cai.

 

Several ways of objection against the argument from the impossibility or “extraspection” of mental states can be attempted.

First, one can attempt to deny that brain states are entirely knowable by external observation without introspection – that is, to admit that there are some brain states that are unknowable by external observation and are knowable only introspectively. However, this possibility contradicts materialism (in the usual sense) and presupposes property dualism (either in the panpsychist or the emergentist version)[14]; to take this way means to admit that the brain has

not only properties (states) that are eventually reducible to the dynamics (including its regularities) of changes of spatial locations of physical bodies (down to the smallest microparticles) and, because of this, knowable by external observation without introspection – that is, material (physical) properties (states) in the usual sense of the concept of material (physical)

but also properties (states) that are unknowable by external observation (because of their principal irreducibility to the dynamics of changes of spatial locations of physical bodies and regularities of this dynamics) and knowable only introspectively – that is, nonphysical mental properties (states) in the usual sense of the concept of nonphysical-mental.

Second, one can attempt to deny the existence of introspection by appealing to arguments like those advanced by John Searle in the book The Rediscovery of the Mind. I think that this way is absolutely hopeless because Searle’s arguments, in fact, have nothing to do with the existence of a special cognitive capacity that does not involve external observation and by which we know about our sensations, emotions, desires, thoughts (whether we choose to call this capacity “introspection” or somehow otherwise). Searle’s arguments show only that the seemingly presupposed by the notion of introspection (Latin for “look inside”) analogy with vision can be misleading because the cognitive capacity by which we know about our mental states is really not “a capacity modeled on vision”, “just like vision only less colourful”. Of course “looking inside” is a metaphor, and like any metaphor, it can mislead if one takes it not metaphorically but literally. As Searle himself writes, “[t]he problem … is not with the ordinary use of the notion of introspection, but with our urge as philosophers to take the metaphor literally”.[15]

Third, one can attempt to deny that mental states are unknowable by external observation without introspection and to contend that we can know about mental states by external observation without knowing that this knowledge is about mental states because the knowledge of mental states obtainable by external observation is not under mentalistic but under physical or neurophysiological descriptions. This objection corresponds to the influential materialistic theory of representationism, which is discussed below.

 

The Same Thing Seen from Different Points of View?

Against Representationism

Helen: We learn about physical processes by external observation (mostly by sight and partially by touch). Observable objects are characterized by size, form, and so on – generally, by a certain spatial location and its changes with time (movements). Unlike this, we know about mental states and processes – sensations, emotions, desires, and thoughts – in an entirely different way called introspection. We do not see, and we cannot palpate sensations, emotions, desires, and thoughts. We merely know about them because we feel, experience, wish, and think them. They have no size, form, and relative spatial location. It is nonsense to say about a feeling, desire, or thought that it is of the square form and has the size of 1 m×1 m or something of the sort. The mental states and processes have properties that the physical objects do not have – for example, the specific subjective character of sensations and emotions (“how-it-feels”) and the contents of thoughts (their “aboutness”)[16]. And they have no physical properties – size, form, and relative spatial location. Thus, it seems quite obvious to me that we have to do with entirely different things – things of utterly different nature.

Mike: However, is not it possible that the same properties are differently represented in the mind? In one case, they are perceived through the “prism” of sight, in the other – through the “prism” of introspection. The “prisms” are so different that “pictures”-representations look entirely different, although the thing represented is the same.

It may be that in the case of the mind and the brain, the same thing is merely perceived by us in two different ways – introspectively and through external observation. The perceptions are different, but they are perceptions of the same thing. Just as our perceptions of colours are quite unlike to what physics tells about colours.

Helen: The first point we need to pay attention to is that a thing and its representation are not the same “thing” but two different “things”. It is so even in the cases of physical representations or informational representations on physical carriers. For example, a mini-model of a plane is a representation of a plane, but you cannot fly on it from New York to Paris. A draft of a plane – whether on paper or on an electronic carrier – is also quite unsuitable for such a flight.

Or let us consider the following example. I have a folder on which cover the words “Muhammad Ali” are written. It contains information about Muhammad Ali – his sports achievements, photos, and so on. This folder is a representation of Muhammad Ali. Now, if someone seriously contended and insisted that the folder is Muhammad Ali, I would think that he went mad. However, this is exactly the kind of contention that materialists-representationists make about the brain and the mind.

If we suppose that feelings are subjective representations of some structures of the brain, this means that they are something different from these structures of the brain; besides, they belong to the mind, not to the physical world, because they have nonphysical properties (and do not have physical properties).

The representations you were talking about – whether visual or introspective – are not physical representations but mental, phenomenal subjective representations, which belong not to physical reality but to the mind. If there is a mind capable of representing things subjectively in different ways, then it is really possible that the same thing (in particular, a certain brain structure) may be subjectively represented in several entirely different ways so that the different subjective representations will have no common properties. However, in physical reality – in particular, in the brain – there are no subjective representations. There is only grey jelly stuff that consists of microscopic material particles moving in various directions. If you see or imagine a tree, there is a subjective image-representation of the tree in your mind. However, there are no subjective images in the brain – there are only various neural structures and chemical processes. Of course, some of these structures can be regarded as a physical representation of the tree in the brain, but this physical representation-structure in the brain will have no common properties with the phenomenal representation-image in the mind.

For example, if you feel pain, there are certain structures in your brain that correspond to the feeling; thus, the feeling of pain can be regarded as a representation of these brain structures. Let us now imagine that someone (perhaps, you) sees these brain structures through a scanning device. Thus, he has (you have) another – visual – representation of the same brain structures. However, both these representations – the feeling of pain and the visual image of the brain structures – are mental-phenomenal-subjective, not physical, representations; they belong to the mind (the first – to the mind of a person who feels pain; the second – to the mind of a person who visually observes the brain structures) and have no physical properties, whereas the thing they represent – the brain structures – is part of physical reality and has only physical properties.

Visual representations, just as well as introspective representations, have no physical properties. I see a table with a rectangular surface of 1 m×2 m. However, the image of this table in my mind is not another physical thing with a rectangular surface 1 m×2 m; it is not present in physical reality at all, and it is nonsensical to attribute it, as well as any other mental state, with geometrical sizes.

Thus, representationism cannot possibly rescue materialism.

******

I think that the theory of “the same thing seen from different points of view” can be consistently defended only be idealists, not by materialists.

It is possible that our minds may perceive the same thing in entirely different ways so that the knowledge we obtain in one way does not translate into the knowledge we obtain in another way. However, this would mean that the knowledge at issue (at least on one side, although more consistently on both sides) is not knowledge about the thing but knowledge about our perceptions of the thing – about subjective experiences evoked in us by the thing.

Let us suppose that there is a thing A that we can perceive in two ways – introspective I and external E. Let us designate our experience of introspective perception of A as I(A) and our experience of external perception of A as E(A). Because I(A) and E(A) are not “the same thing”, our knowledge of I(A) and our knowledge of E(A) will be different in such a way that it is possible to have the full knowledge about I(A) while knowing nothing about E(A), and vice versa. However, in such a perspective, there is no knowledge of A itself – there is only knowledge of our experiences evoked by A.

A reader familiar with the history of philosophy will easily recognize in the above account Immanuel Kant’s theory: our knowledge is not about things-in-themselves but about their appearances, phenomena – the way things appear through the prism of the basic (common to all mankind) structures of the human mind. However, this theory is incompatible with materialism because in it, the primary reality is the mind with its different forms of subjective perception, whereas physical reality in-itself, if it exists, is unknowable.

If (as materialists contend) there is only physical reality, the theory about “the same thing seen from different points of view” is inconsistent. There cannot be different forms of subjective perceptual experience; there cannot be subjective experience at all, for there is no mind, no subject of experience (the self) to begin with. There is nothing but physical space with bodies located in it, changing their spatial locations relative to one another (moving) and influencing one another’s movements in certain regular ways according to the laws of physics, without any – whether introspective or external-sensual – subjective experiences and subjective awareness whatsoever.

Materialists and dualists (unlike Kant), in the overwhelming majority, share the commonsense assumption that in the case of external perceptions, our experience and cognitive capacities enable us to know not only about our subjective experiences but also about those things and processes that evoke these experiences while existing (occurring) independently of them. That is, from the experiences of external observation E(A), we can know about A itself. However, from “introspective perceptionI(A), where A is supposed to be some brain state, we cannot know about A anything at all.

Introspection gives us knowledge about our experiences but gives no knowledge about brain states (structures and processes). However attentively you introspect some of your experience (e.g., the feeling of pain), you cannot obtain any knowledge about the brain structures and processes that underlie the experience. Even if we regard an experience I as an introspectively knowable mental representation of some brain state A, what is introspectively knowable is not A but its mental representation – that is, the experience evoked by A in the mind. If A is some my or your brain state (certain physical structures and processes in my or your brain) and ²(A) is my or your experience evoked by this state (a mental representation of this state in my or your mind), then A and ²(A) are not the same thing.

In effect, we have returned to the earlier discussed point about primary and secondary properties. On the one hand, there is A – primary, own, physical properties of the brain – properties of the brain in-itself. These primary properties are corresponded with secondary, relational properties, which belong not to the brain in-itself but to the brain in its relation to the mind – properties to evoke in the mind some subjective experiences ²(A). However, this is possible only given the existence of two “poles”: on the one hand, the brain in which physical processes A occur that evoke experiences ²(A) in the mind, on the other – the mind (self) that subjectively experiences ²(A) and knows it introspectively.

In principle, different perceptions of the same thing may be so different that from one perception, nothing can be known about another. But all perceptions belong to the mind (or the self) that is capable of subjective experiencing and of being aware of its experiences – not to the brain as a complex system of atoms that merely move and interact by the laws of physics, automatically, having no subjective experiences and awareness.

(Other aspects of the issue “the same thing seen from different points of view” are discussed in Section 4.)

A Strange Capitulation of Frank Jackson

The most widely discussed version of the knowledge argument was proposed by the Australian philosopher Frank Jackson. It is the mental experiment we have discussed earlier – about the physicist Mary who lived up to mature age in a room with special black-and-white lighting (for convenience sake, I have replaced it with a contact film on Mary’s eyes; the “rainbow” version with changing colours is mine), and now, she leaves the room and learns what it is like to have colour perceptions. After a long discussion, Jackson eventually had given up and joined materialists. He has agreed with the answer to Mary’s problem given by the materialistic theory of representationism. Is the representationist (purported) solution really satisfactory? I think that it is not.

Representationism “solves” the problem of Mary in the way we discussed in the previous subsection: “We have to do not with knowledge about two different things but with two different forms of representations of the same thing.” I think that this “solution” is good for nothing. Of course, it can be said that there are certain brain states that are “represented” for Mary at first by external observations, pictures of the brain, scientific theories, etc., and then by her own sensations of colour. But how can this rescue materialism? On the contrary, this reasoning in effect supports dualism, because it leaves us eventually with “things” of two different natures – physical and mental:

1)      the physical events of there being some structures and processes in the brain;

2)      their mental “representations” (subjective states and processes):

2.1) black-and-white visual images and thinking-learning-understanding of theories;

2.2) sensations-experiences of colour perception.

If we choose to call subjective experiences and thinking-understanding by the word “representation”, and if, in some sense, they really represent some physical processes and states of the brain, they do not cease to be subjective experiences and processes (mental states) distinct from those physical processes and states that they represent.

Or may be these “representations” are just some other physical events in the brain? If you say so, you will just superimpose one physical representation upon another but will leave out exactly what is at issue – mental “representations” – those having subjective character. You will just lose sight of the mental (subjective, phenomenal), instead of explaining it. You can multiply these physical representations ad infinitum, but on this way you cannot ever reach subjective experiences. If the representations involved are but physical states and processes in the brain (i.e., a huge multitude of atoms, which experience nothing, do not think, and have no awareness, which are just located and moving and influencing one another’s movements in some very complicated structured ways), there can be (physical) representations, representations of representations, representations of representations of representations, and so on ad infinitum, without any subjective experiencing and awareness.

Self-contradiction of Materialism as a Theory of the Identity of Mental and Physical States

Materialists often explain their theory by the statement that human sensations, emotions, desires, thoughts, etc. actually are physical processes (i.e., some spatial structures and movements) in the brain but appear to us as subjective experiences devoid of spatial properties. In other words, what appears to us as sensations, emotions, desires, thoughts, etc. are merely mental “representations” of some physical (or functional[17]) states. Materialists somehow fail to notice that such an explanation of the materialistic theory is self-contradictory; it refutes materialism. In effect, this “explanation” admits that besides the physical (functional) processes and states, that is, in addition to physical reality, there is also the realm of subjectivity – a sort of “phenomenal space” to which those “appearances” (what appears-seems to us how it appears-seems to us), mental “representations”, belong. This “phenomenal space” is the mind. Thus, the mind does not belong to physical reality – it is something besides, in addition to physical reality. However, this is the theory of dualism (in the most general outlines, leaving aside specifics of various subdivisions).

The physical processes in the brain that correspond to certain sensations, desires, thoughts, etc. cannot be the same thing as their mental “representations” (that is, sensations, desires, thoughts proper) how they are subjectively experienced and how we are subjectively aware of them.

The only possibility to defend materialism consistently is to deny the existence of the realm of subjectivity – that is, the mind proper (in the ordinary sense of this word, to be distinguished from the mind’s behavioural manifestations and contribution to the functioning of the organism).

From the Knowledge Argument to the Zombie Argument

Joseph Levine[18] explains the existence and unsolvability” (in the sense of a satisfactory materialistic solution) of the mind-body problem as follows. If we accept the materialistic thesis of the identity of a certain experience (e.g., pain) with some physical processes in the brain (e.g., with the excitement of C-fibers), we are unable to explain why these physical processes have such, not some other, a qualitative phenomenal character, that is, why it is subjectively experienced as it does and not somehow otherwise (e.g., why the excitement of C-fibers is subjectively experienced as painful, not as pleasant).[19] The knowledge argument expresses this problem. However, David Chalmers rightly suggests that this problem is not the most fundamental.

The knowledge argument shows that specific mental facts – facts about a specific phenomenal character of an experience (painful, not pleasant) – do not belong to the whole multitude of all physical (in the wide sense) facts, are not logically determined by (contained in) the facts about physical processes that correspond to these experiences.

However, there is a more fundamental problem that concerns not the qualitative specifics of various mental states (subjective experiences) but their existence qua mental, subjective states: why something is subjectively experienced at all? In particular, why the excitement of C-fibers is somehow (it does not matter how) subjectively experienced?

Thus, materialism is confronted with two problems that are unsolvable for it:

1) The problem of the qualitative specifics of mental (subjective, phenomenal) states: how to explain that when having some specific physical states of the brain, we have those specific subjective experiences which we have, not some other?

2) The problem of the existence of mental (subjective, phenomenal) states: how to explain that we have subjective experiences at all (whereas it seems that we could have no)? This problem, the most fundamental and unsolvable for materialism, consists in the fact that we are beings who subjectively experience and are subjectively aware, not humanoid phenomenal zombies who physically do (in the sense of externally observable behaviour – movements of the body) all the same things that we do, and in whose bodies all the same physical structures and movements occur, but all this happens purely automatically (mechanically), without any subjective experiences and awareness whatsoever. In more details, we will discuss the problem of phenomenal zombies in the next section.



[1] Law S. What Is the Mind?

[2] Jackson F. Epiphenomenal Qualia; Jackson F. What Mary didn’t know?

[3] She knows what these experiences are like, and she can identify them in her own private language as “monday sensation”, “tuesday sensation”, etc. She just cannot express this knowledge in public language (cannot correlate her private language with public language).

[4] Cf.: C.McGinn: “The uniqueness of the brain among physical objects will never be revealed from the perceptual standpoint of brain science. If all we had to go on was brain science, we would never even guess that the brain houses consciousness at all. The way we know that it does house consciousness is ultimately through introspection... It is because changes in, and injuries to, the brain result in changes in consciousness, as revealed to the faculty of introspective awareness, that we select the brain as the seat of consciousness. Aristotle believed that the heart was the seat of consciousness; he was wrong simply because it is the brain, not the heart, whose activity correlates most directly with what happens in consciousness. The best way for a brain surgeon to decide what parts of your brain produce what mental states is to keep you awake during surgery and ask you what you are experiencing as he probes about in your cerebral crevices. We know that the brain is the seat of consciousness ultimately because changes in the brain correlate most directly with how our mind seems to us from the inside.” (McGinn C. The Mysterious Flame. – pp. 52-53)

[5] This holds even for the statements about perceptions of physical bodies (as things of a certain size, form, and location – bearers of spatial characteristics) – as far as the perceptions themselves, not the things perceived, are concerned. Such statements do not bear physical information about perceptions. Of course, they may bear physical information about the things perceived. If I say: “I see a table with a square surface approximately 1 m×1 m nearly a meter to the left of myself”, this statement, probably, indirectly bears the information about the location, form, and size of the table, but it does not bear information about the location, form, and size of my sensual perception of the table (or about the physical neural-brain structures and processes responsible for the perception).

[6] Of course, if, besides the knowledge about physical processes in the brain, we have additional knowledge of specific correlations-correspondences between such physical processes and subjective experiences, then we can obtain (infer) the knowledge about subjective experiences. And vice versa, if we have knowledge about subjective experiences plus additional knowledge about specific correspondences between physical processes in the brain and subjective experiences, then we can obtain (infer) knowledge about physical processes in the brain. However, this additional knowledge is unobtainable from within the knowledge about the physical alone, as well as from within the knowledge of subjective experiences alone; it is obtainable only through the juxtaposition of the former with the latter. The need for such additional, connecting knowledge, which is obtainable only through juxtaposition of the two sides, means that these two sides are not the same, and therefore, the dualism is true.

[7] Hofstadter D., Dennett D. (eds.) The Mind’s I. – p. 387.

[8] Hofstadter D., Dennett D. (eds.) The Mind’s I. – p. 387.

[9] In: Law S. The Philosophy Gym

[10] Churchland P. Matter and Consciousness. – p. 32.

[11] Churchland P. Matter and Consciousness. – p. 32.

[12] Churchland P. Matter and Consciousness. – p. 33.

[13] Churchland P. Matter and Consciousness. – p. 33.

[14] In more details about emergentist property dualism, see Book 2, Section 9, subsection “Property Dualism and Emergentism”; about the necessity for this theory of the recognition of the unique radically emergent character of the mind, see Section 6, subsections “Materialistic Emergentism” and “David Chalmers about Emergence”; about panpsychism and problems it engenders, see Book 2, Section 9 subsection “Dualism and Panpsychism” and Section 11, subsection “Conceptual Mess of Russellianism”.

[15] Searle J. The Rediscovery of the Mind. – p. 144.

[16] For more details on “aboutness”, see Section 5.

[17] The most influential modern branch of materialism – functionalism – interprets the mind not directly in terms of physical processes but in terms of functions for an organism; it emphasizes that the same functions may have different physical realizations (by analogy with computer programs, software, as distinct from the physical structure and matter of computer, hardware).

[18] J. Levine is a modern philosopher somewhere at the crossroads of materialism and dualism. Despite his materialistic belief, Levine has formulated and argued for the thesis that there is “the explanatory gap” between the physical and the mental and that no known materialistic approach can overcome it. The thesis is one of the most discussed in the modern philosophy of mind.

[19] Levine J. Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap

[Return to Content]

[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]