[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]

[Return to Content]

11. Splintered Mind, Russellianism and Determinism

 

How to Relegate "Quantum Zombies"?

The Ineluctability of Indivisible Mental Subject

Against the Notions of Subjectless Experience and Compound Mind

In the article "Moving Forward on the Problem of Consciousness" (written a year after "The Conscious Mind") Chalmers develops the argument about "subtraction of a phenomenal component", and supplements it with some new considerations favourable to "the Russellian view". The view is the direction in modern philosophy of mind which is, in fact, panpsychism, but is most often called "Russellian monism" – in honour of Bertrand Russell, who has formulated the basic ideas which modern supporters of this direction try to develop. Chalmers uses a more neutral name "the Russellian view", as he remarks that in a certain important respect this conception is dualistic. Further on I will name it "russellianism". In the context of the current discussion, "russellianism" looks sort of "the third way" between interactionism and epiphenomenalism: like interactionism, russellianism (as if) admits the causal efficiency of the mind; but in a paradoxical way combines this with acceptance of the thesis about the causal closure of physical reality.

In keeping with his arguments from "The Conscious Mind" which we have discussed in the Appendix to the previous chapter, Chalmers suggests that "an appeal to ³nteract³on³st dualism does not really solve the problems of epiphenomenalism", since "³nteract³on³sm is subject to an epiphenomenalist worry of its own": "for any given ³nteract³on³st theory, it seems that we can remove the facts about experience, and still be left with a coherent causal story." Chalmers illustrates this thesis on the examples of interactionist theories of J.Eccles and G.Stapp:

“Take Eccles' theory on which "psychons" in the mind affect physical processes in the brain. Here one can tell a perfectly coherent causal story about psychons and their effect on the brain without ever mentioning the fact that psychons are experiential. On this story, psychons will be viewed as causal entities analogous to electrons and protons in physical theories, affected by certain physical entities and affecting them in turn; and just as with protons and electrons, the fact that psychons have any experiential qualities will be quite inessential to the dynamic story.”

“Consider Stapp's view… Presumably when this view is filled out, it will say that certain physical states P give rise to certain experiential states E, and that these states E bring about physical collapses[1] in turn… Given that physics works as Stapp suggests, there is a logically possible world with a "quantum zombie". In this world, instead of P causing experience E which causes collapse, P causes collapse directly. There is no consciousness in this world, but all the functions are performed just the same. So there is a sense in which the fact that experience is associated with collapses in our world is superfluous.”

From these examples, Chalmers generalizes:

“one can tell a similar conceptually coherent "zombie" story for any interactionist picture”.

I think that this generalization is disputable.

In the examples adduced by Chalmers, as he describes them in the above quotations, there is one characteristic common feature: interactionism is depicted not as a theory about interaction between the brain and the mental self (the mind) as a unitary indivisible whole, but as a theory about interaction between the brain and some purported elements of the mind. In the case of Eccles’ theory the brain is supposed to interact with some entities called psychons; in the case of what Chalmers thinks “Stapp's view … will say … presumably when this view is filled out” – with some entities called "experiences" – as if these "experiences" exist and interact with the brain on their own, without the experiencer – the subject who experiences them. (Obviously, we have to do with the influence of the absurd David Hume’s theory that the self is but a "bundle" of "experiences". – See section 8.)

Accordingly, I think that Chalmers’ argument is applicable to those versions of interactionism which splinter the mind in such a way. But it is doubtful that the argument is applicable to "holistic" interactionism (such as, for example, interactionism of R.Descartes and K.Popper, and correctly interpreted theories Eccles and Stapp[2]), in which the mental self (the mind) is understood as an indivisible whole, the unitary mental subject interacting with the brain. It is not obvious at all that for such interactionism “one can tell a similar conceptually coherent "zombie" story”.

 

To see that such a story-telling is problematical, let us consider a general scheme presupposed by Chalmers’ reasoning. It concerns with the following causal chain:

1) a physical event A in a physical system S causes a certain mental state;

2) this mental state, in its turn, effects a certain causal influence C on physical events in system S.

Thus, the mental state acts in the role of a generator of additional causal dynamics in system S. (Likewise, this role may be acted by some simple mental entities like Eccles’ psychons.) But the same additional causal dynamics may be realised just as well by some physical entity.

Prima facie, it may seem that it makes no principal difference whether the role of mental generators of physical causality is implemented by mental entities like psychons or separate simple experiences, or it is implemented by such a mental entity as a human mind. In any case, there is some physical event as input of the generator, and some causal physical dynamics as output. As both input and output are physical, the same transformation could be, in principle, accomplished by some physical entity. But on a better thought we may see that there is a difference which makes a principal difference.

To begin with, let us notice that “a conceptually coherent "zombie" story” we are interested in should be a story not about a single concrete case (a physical event Art in a certain spatial region r at a certain moment of time t has caused a certain experience, which has caused a certain causal physical dynamics Crt), but about an infinite, open multitude of all such cases together. In “a conceptually coherent "zombie" story” the physical mediator-generator should be a causally equivalent replacement of the mind not for one concrete piece of experience associated with one concrete brain, but for the whole human mind throughout the whole human life. But such a causally equivalent replacement may well happen to be impossible.

Admittedly, for any physical description of physical event Àrt and causal dynamics Crt, such a physical entity (or system) is possible that if it receives Àrt as input, it generates Crt as output. But not for any (especially, infinite) multitude of pairs {(Àrt1, Crt1), (Àrt2, Crt2)..., (Àrtn, Crtn)} such a physical entity (system) is possible. For example, it is possible that minds of different people, or a mind of one person at different moments of his/her life react(s) differently on identical input physical events Àrt1 and, accordingly, generate(s) different causal dynamics as output; and this happens not as a matter of chance (chance events could be realized in a physical system, – for example, by quantum-mechanical processes), but as a consequence of differences between minds of different people (uniqueness of each person’s mind), and as a consequence of the dynamics of states and development of a person’s mind throughout his/her life. That one could tell about all this “a conceptually coherent "zombie" story”, the physical entity (system) intended as a causal replacement for the mind should, firstly, be unique for every person and, secondly, should by means of its own (physical) causality change-develop in such a way that it would precisely parallel infinitely complex dynamics of the development and changes of states of an individual human mind. It is by no means obvious that such a physical entity (system) is possible.

However, we need to admit that though such a possibility is problematical, it is nonetheless not excluded, in principle. In fact, epiphenomenalism is a hypothesis that such dynamics and development of the physical system of the brain actually take place, and the mind just passively reflects the dynamics of processes in the brain. To adjudicate which one of the competing hypotheses – epiphenomenalism or interactionism – is preferable, additional arguments are needed; and I propose such arguments (which testify against epiphenomenalism, in favour of interactionism) in the main part of the previous section. What I wrote above in this section is not an argument against epiphenomenalism, but a rebuttal of Chalmers’ argument purported to show that interactionism “does not really solve the problems of epiphenomenalism”, “is subject to an epiphenomenalist worry of its own”, since “for any given interactionist theory, it seems that we can remove the facts about experience, and still be left with a coherent causal story”. As he/she understands the human self as a noncompound-indivisible mental subject, an interactionist can avoid “an epiphenomenalist worry”, since it is very doubtful that that we can remove from a person’s life-story all the facts about his/her (subjective) sensations, emotions, thoughts, desires and intentions, and will still be left with a coherent causal story. (Let us recollect the stories from the main part of the previous section about Plato, his readers, admirers and critics, about Einstein and his books on the relativity theory, about theatrical public etc.)

 

The Conceptual Mess of Russellianism

Chalmers’ further reasoning, in which he passes from epiphenomenalism to russellianism, are impregnated with the same mistake – the assumptions of the compound mind and of subjectless experience.

Chalmers admits that the interactionist has a reasonable solution to the problem of “an epiphenomenalist worry”:

“Presumably, the interactionist will respond that some nodes in the causal network are experiential through and through. Even though one can tell the causal story about psychons without mentioning experience, for example, psychons are intrinsically experiential all the same. Subtract experience, and there is nothing left of the psychon but an empty place-marker in a causal network, which is arguably to say there is nothing left at all. To have real causation, one needs something to do the causing; and here, what is doing the causing is experience.”

Chalmers admits that this solution is “perfectly reasonable”, but suggests that “the same solution will work in a causally closed physical world”:

“Just as the interactionist postulates that some nodes in the causal network are intrinsically experiential, the "epiphenomenalist" can do the same.”

Let's notice, that in this statement "epiphenomenalist" is taken in inverted commas. In fact, epiphenomenalist (without inverted commas) cannot "do the same", for it won’t be epiphenomenalism any more. By definition, epiphenomenalism denies causal efficiency of the mental (experiential). From Chalmers’ further explanations it is clear that an "epiphenomenalist" he writes about is not an epiphenomenalist, but a russellianist.

Chalmers proposes to “exploit an idea that was set out by Bertrand Russell (1926), and which has been developed in recent years by Grover Maxwell (1978) and Michael Lockwood (1989). This is the idea that physics characterizes its basic entities only extrinsically, in terms of their causes and effects, and leaves their intrinsic nature unspecified.” There are some physical entities which causally interact, but what is their intrinsic nature, what are their intrinsic properties? The proposed solution is that “the intrinsic properties underlying physical dispositions are themselves experiential properties, or perhaps they are some sort of proto-experiential properties that together constitute conscious experience. This way, we locate experience inside the causal network that physics describes, rather than outside it as a dangler.”

 

Let's try to examine this idea. Let’s suppose that the physical entities have intrinsic properties, and that these internal properties are "experiential" or "protoexperiential" properties. In that case, there is a further question which needs to be answered: what is the relationship between intrinsic and extrinsic properties? Logically, there are three possibilities:

1) Russellianism-idealism. The physical entities have (as ontologically fundamental) only intrinsic properties; so-called "extrinsic" properties are but manifestations, appearances of intrinsic properties, – how they appear to the human mind (as Kant’s phenomena).

2) Russellianism-epiphenomenalism. The physical entities have both intrinsic and extrinsic properties. Extrinsic properties of physical entities are other properties, distinct from intrinsic. All physical causation is defined by extrinsic properties; this means that intrinsic properties make no contribution to physical causality. At the best, they may be epiphenomena of extrinsic properties. In other words, the physical entities have such extrinsic properties as spatial location, electric charge, mass, etc.; besides, they have also a subjective dimension in which they experience (protoexperience?) – quite passively – some experiences or protoexperiences (it may be that their structure reflects the structure of external interactions). As everything that, as far as we know and can know, happens with quarks, atoms, molecules, etc. is explainable in terms of their "extrinsic" properties, such as spatial location, mass, electric charge, etc., and as we know nothing about their "intrinsic" properties, and can’t know anything about them (have no relevant evidences) – so it seems much more reasonable to assume that quarks, atoms, molecules etc. have only such properties as spatial location, mass, electric charge, etc., and have no subjective experiences! Admittedly, it is possible, in principle, that in each quark there live a huge multitude of fairies and gnomes; alas, we can’t know anything about it, for these fairies and gnomes, firstly, are invisible and, secondly, are tightly closed in their quarks.

3) Russellianism-interactionism. The physical entities have both intrinsic properties and extrinsic properties, and these two kinds of properties interact. In other words, processes which take place in “the subjective dimension” of physical entities (some analogue of human sensations, emotions, thinking, desires etc.) influence their extrinsic properties. However, physics says that such properties as weight and electric charge remain constant. But we can assume (as it was done by some ancient philosophers) that the attraction and repulsion between physical bodies is a consequence of the love and hatred which they experience to each other, and which magnitude happen to obey to a strict mathematical order described by the laws of physics (such, for example, as the gravitational law of love: the force of love between two bodies is directly proportional to their masses and inversely proportional to the squared distance between them☺).

Chalmers’ own attitude with respect to these three alternatives turns out to be confused:

“The Russellian view still qualifies as a sort of "naturalistic dualism", as it requires us to introduce experience or proto-experience as fundamental, and it requires a deep duality between the intrinsic and extrinsic features of physical reality. But underlying this dualism, there is a deeper monism: we have an integrated world of intrinsic properties connected by causal relations.”

This statement makes a contradictory mixture of two different – dualistic and idealistic – versions of russellianism. The statement about “a deep duality between the intrinsic and extrinsic features of physical reality” assumes russellianism-epiphenomenalism or russellianism-interactionism; but it is incompatible with the statement about “an integrated world of intrinsic properties connected by causal relations”, which assumes russellianism-idealism.

Anyway, all these deep metaphysical speculations, unfortunately, help nothing for understanding of that unique mind (consciousness) about existence and properties of which we know, – the human mind (consciousness) and its relation to the body (brain). Whether quarks, atoms and molecules have any minds or not, this tells nothing about my – or your – mind (if not to take into consideration the very implausible hypothesis that the human mind-self is a mind-self of some privileged quark in the human brain).

It has to be mentioned that Chalmers does not leave this problem unnoticed. He acknowledges as an obvious difficulty for russellianism “the problem of how fundamental experiential or proto-experiential properties at the microscopic level somehow together constitute the sort of complex, unified experience that we possess.” Chalmers admits also that interactionist dualism avoids this problem:

“instead of trying to constitute our consciousness out of innumerable different fundamental nodes, there might turn out to be a single node in each case (or just a few?) which carries the burden. … this avoidance of the constitution problem may in the end turn out to be the greatest virtue of a quantum interactionism.” 

 (Let us correct one inaccuracy: the adjective "quantum" has no essential bearing to the issue; it has to be replaced with “holistic” or “unitarian” or "single-noded".)

But Chalmers supposes that, perhaps, russellianism too can avoid this problem somehow. I think that it is impossible: “the constitution problem” is just as unsolvable as the problem of physicalist reduction, for essentially the same reasons. Chalmers manages not to notice this as he deliberates about experience in an absurd Humean key – forgetting about the subject of experience, that experience is possible only as someone's experience, that the very concept of experience necessarily presupposes the existence of the subject of this experience. This mistake – let us designate it as the mistake of subjectless experience – in generally characteristic for russellianism; and it creates a conceptual mess which allows theorists of this direction to jump in their reasoning freely and without noticing between idealism, neutral monism, materialism and dualism.

The mess arises in two points:

1) Between, on one hand, the basic idealistic hypothesis that the physical relations really are relations between intrinsic properties (Chalmers: “a deeper monism: we have an integrated world of intrinsic properties connected by causal relations”), and that these intrinsic properties are mental properties-states, and, on the other hand, reasoning about the relationship between the intrinsic and the extrinsic properties in a dualistic key (Chalmers: “a deep duality between the intrinsic and extrinsic features of physical reality”);

2) between the basic hypothesis that the intrinsic properties are experiential properties-states, and reasoning about "experience" in the Humean key – as if experience exists without an experiencer, a subject who experiences it. If we assume the hypothesis that the internal nature of reality is experience, we take the position of idealism; but arguing about experience as something subjectless, we slide into the position of materialism. To repeat, the concept of experience necessarily presupposes the existence of a subject who experiences it, an experiencer. An experience which is not experienced by anyone is a sheer nonsense. Reality which exists irrespective of whether someone experiences it or not, i.e. independently of the mental subject, is called material or physical reality, not experience. Using the word "protoexperiential" instead of "experiential" only obscures the mess: if this "protoexperience" is subjectively experienced by some mental subject, then the prefix ("proto-") is needless; if not, then "protoexperience" is an objective non-mental reality, i.e. material, physical reality.

After disentangling this mess we are left with a panpsychist hypothesis that the physical entities – such as molecules, atoms, electrons, quarks – are both physical objects and mental subjects experiencing some experiences depending on their relations (interactions) with other such psychophysical entities. (As was explained above, three variants of the relationship between the mental and physical aspects are possible – idealistic, epiphenomenalistic and interactionist.)

Unfortunately, as I have already noted, this hypothesis, as well as Eccles’ hypothesis about the psychons (mental entities interacting with neurons in the brain), gives absolutely nothing for the explanation of that for the sake of what it all was thought out – the mind of that unique kind about existence and properties of which we know, and which creates the mind-body problem – my or your mind-self. Whether psychons exist or not, whether quarks and atoms have minds or not, – these are questions about other mental entities and their minds, but in no way about my (your) mind-self. Subjective experiences of psychons (if they exist), quarks, atoms, molecules etc. (if they experience anything) are their subjective experiences (about which neither me nor you don’t and can’t know anything), not my or your subjective experiences. Logical transition from a multitude of minds of psychons, quarks and atoms (more accurately, from a multitude of such hypothetical mental subjects as psychon-subjects, quark-subjects and atom-subjects, etc.) to my or your mind (more accurately, to my or your selves as mental subjects) is just as impossible as logical transition from a multitude of unconscious quarks, atoms, etc. to my or your minds-selves.

In general, what Chalmers calls “the "combination problem"” or “the "constitution problem"”, admitting that it “is surely the hardest” for russellianism, is not simply a difficult problem, but the hard problem in that specific strong sense in which Chalmers talks of “the hard problem of consciousness” for materialism (see section 6, subsection “The Hard Problem of Consciousness”). You need just understand that “the "constitution problem"” is not a problem of composing complex experience from simple, and a problem of composing the mental subject-self. By paraphrasing Chalmers’ formulation of “the hard problem of consciousness”, we have quite analogously the hard problem of the self for russellianism (panpsychism):

The really hard problem for Russellianism is the problem of the self. It is the problem of my or your experience and subjective awareness, the problem of the existence of me and you (our selves) qua experiencers and subjects of awareness. Even if we suppose that physical entities of which our bodies and brains consist (atoms, molecules, neurons and whatever else) are mental subjects capable of having experiences, there still remain further unanswered questions: Why do me and you have experiences and subjective awareness? Why there are me and you qua experiencers and subjects of awareness? There is an explanatory gap between, on one side, atoms, molecules, neurons etc. qua mental subjects and, on the other side, me and you qua mental subjects. The facts about the existence of me and you qua mental subjects, and about my and your experiences and subjective awareness, cannot be an automatic consequence of any account about atoms, molecules, neurons etc. qua mental subjects, and about their experiences, as it is conceptually coherent that any experiences of atoms, molecules, neurons etc. could exist without there being me and you qua mental subjects. My and your existence qua mental subjects, our experiences and subjective awareness are not entailed by those of atoms, molecules, neurons etc.

Surely, a russellianist (panpsychist) can tread one of the ways quite similar to those which materialists choose. Like the elimativists of the functionalists a la Dennett – what Chalmers describes as “type-A materialism” (denying that there is the phenomenal mind as something which needs explanation besides the functions), – a russellianist can simply deny or ignore the existence of the mental subject, talk of experience as if it exists on its own, without an experiencer. Or, like the supporters of the theory of identity (“type-B materialism” in Chalmers’ terminology), a russellianist (panpsychist) can postulate a “primitive identity” between the human self and some system of psychophysical entities (atoms, molecules, neurons, etc.) composing the brain. Obviously, these strategies are just as unsatisfactory as the corresponding materialistic strategies.

In fact, a panpsychist has yet one possibility with no materialistic analogy. The hard problem of the self for russellianism (panpsychism) arises so far as the russellianist tries to explain the self as a composition of some simpler elements. In principle, a panpsychist can avoid this problem by assuming that the self is not a composition of "quark-subjects", but one of them, i.e. a subject "embodied" in one of the fundamental (noncompound-indivisible) (psycho-)physical entities inside the brain. The problem, however, is that all physical entities (microparticles) known to modern physics seem obviously inadequate for this role.

The role of the most fundamental physical microparticles can be attributed to quarks; however, modern physics says that they do not exist separately, but only as parts of other microparticles. There are billions of quarks in the brain, and there are billions of microparticles of every kind of the next higher level of organisation – electrons, protons, neutrons, etc. They all interact with other microparticles in the brain in a rather simple way according to the laws of physics. This makes them obviously unfit for the role of the self, which is unique and, in the interactionist version, should interact with the brain in a very complex way which would correspond to the complexity of the mental structure and dynamics of the self.

Alternatively, if we admit that the selves are some unknown to modern physics fundamental entities capable of all the phenomenal complexity of the human mind and interacting with other (physical) elements of the brain, then attribution of mentality to physical entities loses any sense, and we arrive at usual dualism-interactionism.

 

Interactionism and the Problem of Determinism: How to Relegate Laplace’s Demon?

The Russian philosopher V.Vasilyev has offered his version of solution of the mind-body problem which in some sense contrives to combine interactionism with the causal closure of physical reality.[3] In fact, this sense essentially differs from what is usually understood by “the causal closure of the physical”. The gist is as follows. On the one hand, we are proposed to assume 1) causal efficiency of the mind. On the other hand, we a proposed to assume 2) determinism as the doctrine that every event is unequivocally predetermined by previous events (here and further on I am talking about comprehensive determinism, which excludes the possibility of any non-predetermined events), and 3) the thesis (corresponding to the scientific view of the development of the Universe) that there was a time when no mind existed – there was nothing but physical reality. If put together, these three assumptions yield the following result: though the mind is causally efficient, influences physical events, but its causal contribution is entirely a necessary consequence of the preceding physical causation (which have produced the mind and all its various states); so, in fact, all in physical reality (and in the mind too) is eventually unequivocally predetermined by some preceding physical causes (events, states).[4] Laplace’s demon, having learnt all physical facts about the world at some moment of time before mind has first emerged (for example, after a microsecond after the Big Bang), and knowing all physical and psychophysical laws of nature, could exactly predict all – physical and mental alike – events, states of a physical reality and of all existing minds at any subsequent moment of time.

V.Vasilyev doesn’t merely propose this as a hypothesis, but contends that this theory necessarily follows from fundamental, necessary structures (concepts, presumptions) of human thinking. However, the substantiation of this claim he offers is, in my opinion, unsound; it contains several mistakes, any one of which is enough to invalidate the substantiation. I will discuss only the first of them; firstly, because all further steps of the substantiation are based on the results of this first (mistaken, in my opinion) step; secondly, because it is most directly connected with the problem discussed in this subsection.

Vasilyev’s substantiation relies on “analyzing how people conceive of facts”, which “in a general outline … was performed by David Hume way back in the 18th century”. This analysis tells that “people … ascribe dif­ferent properties to things and living creatures surrounding them”, and this attribution of properties “boils down to the expecta­tion that some or other thing will "behave" in an appropriate way under certain circumstances”. In their turn, “expectations form on the basis of past experience trans­ferred to the future”, and “this transfer is based on belief in the identity of past and future”, which Hume considered as “a primary prin­ciple of human nature”.[5] It is a pity that Vasilyev does not call into question correctness of Hume’s analysis and conclusions, and does not consider alternative views, – in particular, Karl Popper's views to which I will address below. Accepting uncritically Hume’s conclusions, – which are, at least, doubtful, – Vasilyev continues:

Belief in the past-future identity, as I see it, is a direct expression of the structure of human con­sciousness. we simply have no material for the building of a reliable image of the future other than memories of sequences of past events, something that signifies precisely belief in the identity of past and future. … Since belief in the identity of past and future is necessarily integrated in the very structure of consciousness, it is inevitable for us.[6]

All this is doubtful in the higher measure. From my point of view, the thesis about the identity of past and future is a foggy philosophical postulate which does not expresses adequately common human notions about the relations of past and future, as these notions really are, and, even more so, does not express something necessary, inevitable, such that all people necessarily believe in it, can not help believing in it.

To begin with, noone of us believes in the identity of past and future in the literal sense. Future is not past, and past is not future. Also, noone believes in the identity of past and future in the sense that tomorrow or the day after tomorrow will be in every respect exactly the same as yesterday or the day before yesterday. (Rather, we will agree that every moment of time, if taken in its entirety, is unique and unrepeatable.) When talking about the identity of past and future, Vasilyev (and Hume) mean something different. What is it? It turns out, nothing else than determinism:

“… belief in the past-future identity is equiva­lent to believing that each event has a cause. … we believe that a repetition of all components of a past event (including its configuration) will bring in its wake the same combined event as before.[7]

Let us notice first, that is absolutely unclear, what can “a repetition of all components of a past event (including its configuration)” mean. Such a repetition (at least, within the history of mankind and all the history of the Universe after the Big Bang) simply never happens, for “all components of a past event (including its configuration)” include the whole world.

Now let us consider the questions: is it really the case that all people believe (and always believed) that “each event has a cause”? And is it really the case that this belief is necessary, inevitable for us, so that we all can’t help believing in it? I think that both these contentions don’t correspond with reality.

I think that if all people of all times and cultures were asked the question whether they believe that “each event has a cause” or, in other words, that nothing genuinely accidental ever happens, and that all human desires and actions are predetermined unequivocally down to all the smallest details by preceding states of the Universe, we would get different answers from different people. So, if it is a question of conscious belief, then many may be, even the majority – of people do not believe in determinism.

But perhaps all people believe in determinism in the sense of subconscious belief as something they follow involuntarily in their thinking and actions? It is extremely doubtfully. I think that unbiased consideration of how common people in their daily life think about causality, necessity and chance in various cases and situations would show that this reasoning is often, perhaps even usually, but not always deterministic, that much of this reasoning contains indeterministic assumptions both in the sense of genuine chance (something that is genuinely accidental, not just seems accidental in the light of our incomplete knowledge) and in the sense of a human free will.

Even more obviously false is the statement that the belief in determinism is necessary, inevitable for the human person. Many philosophers do reject determinism. Modern microphysics (quantum mechanics), in its "orthodox interpretation”, as well as in some unorthodox interpretations, rejects determinism. Vasilyev himself, when writing about quantum mechanics, admits indeterminism. But if it is possible to believe in indeterminism at the microlevel, then why can’t one believe that at macrolevel, too, not everything is entirely deterministic?!

Logically, there are no reasons to deny the possibility of causeless events. True, for many people it is hard to understand: how can it be, how is it possible that something happens so, not somehow otherwise, without any cause at all? Formerly, this was a problem for me too. It was solved when I have noticed that in is similar to the situation with logically possible worlds. Let us recollect Leibnitz: our world is one of the infinite multitude of logically possible worlds. Suppose, we ask: why our world has happened to be such as it is, not somehow otherwise how it could be (with some quite different laws of nature and structure)? – No answer to this question exists. There is no any "because". It just happened to be such, without any cause whatever. But if it is possible with respect to the whole Universe, then, in principle, it may be possible also with respect to some its parts, events, etc.

If so, what is the alternative to Hume’s views about causality? Karl Popper proposes to consider the concept of causality as derivative from the concept of regularities or laws of nature.[8] What we all really necessarily believe in (in the sense of notions by which we are usually guided in our daily life and thinking), and what is necessary for development of knowledge (in particular, of science) is 1) the existence of invariable regularities which operate in past, present and future, irrespective of our desires, – the laws of nature and 2) our ability in the process “trials and errors”, “conjectures and refutations” to create and improve theories which rather well (better and better with new improvements) "grasp" these regularities-laws. Determination by the laws of nature needn’t necessarily to be absolutely comprehensive; there are no reasons to exclude the possibility of some non-predetermined events. (Surely, such epistemology is incompatible with Hume’s associative psychology; it assumes creative-searching character of the process of cognition, “the searchlight theory of consciousness”, as opposed to what Popper criticised under names “observationism” and “the bucket theory of consciousness”.[9])

So, we can see that determinism and belief in it are not necessary at all. Accordingly, V.Vasilyev’s hypothesis of deterministic interactionism is no more than a hypothesis. From my point of view, this is not its drawback, for (as Popper convincingly – for me, at least – argued) nothing more than a hypothesis exist in philosophy, as well as in empirical science. However, as there is an alternative, indeterministic hypothesis, so we are to try to form a clear notions about the available alternatives, estimate pro's and con's each of them, and in this light to make up our own opinions-preferences.

 

The main objection against the theory of determinism is that it deprives of sense the most important – necessary for a meaningful human life and action – human notions – the notions of freedom as real possibility of choice and of responsibility for the choice made. As I have already remarked, from the point of view of determinism, everything that any person ever did, does or will do is unequivocally and necessarily predetermined by physical states of the Universe at any arbitrary moment of time before the emergence of the first consciousness, – for example, the totality of physical states of the Universe (the totality of physical facts about the Universe) at the time of a second after the Bing Bang. Hence, the human person is not really the author of his/her actions, and cannot be considered as responsible for them. It just seems to a person that he/she makes choices among really existing possibilities; the truth is that every his/her choice is predetermined in all the smallest details long before his/her birth. We all are just puppets who have the illusion of deciding something. Eventually, the "author" of all that happens, including all human actions, is the Big Bang; however, the concepts of freedom and responsibility are hardly applicable to it.

In such a perspective, efficiency of the mind, consciousness is similar to efficiency of a hammer driving in nails. Really, it is a human person who drives in nails using the hammer, which he/she or some other human person has earlier manufactured, as a tool. On assumption of determinism, the mind, consciousness is such a tool manufactured by physical processes in the brain (or, indirectly, by the Big Bang) and completely operated by them, though this tool has also subjective-phenomenal dimension in which it has an illusion that it behaves on its own choice, on its free will. (Perhaps, it seems to a hammer too that it drives in nails because it has chosen to do it.)

 

On the other hand, it seems that indeterminism of a quantum-mechanic sort (in some situation there is some spectrum of real possibilities with a certain distribution of predispositions-probabilities of realisation; which of them will be actually realised is a matter of genuine chance) hardly helps. After all, if a person does something just accidentally, it has as little to do with freedom and responsibility as actions of a person-puppet predetermined by the Big Bang. However it can seem that, logically, no third alternative exists – any action of a person, or any detail of action is either predetermined, or not.

This alternative consists in that some complex dynamic interweaving of deterministic and indeterministic events forms a complex qualitative profile (temperament, character, ideas, knowledge, values, belief) of a human person, whose choices become causes of his/her actions, and also of the dynamics of his/her own subsequent development.

Let us begin with the moment of birth. According to one of non-naturalistic versions of dualism (theistic-creationist dualism), God creates a person’s soul and accommodates it in a body. According to another (the theory of reincarnations) – a soul, which has earlier lived through many other lives in other bodies, gets associated with (embodied in) a new body (and loses explicit memory of her previous lives). In both versions, a soul, i.e. a human mental self, from the very birth can possess many individual properties (dispositions) considerably independent of its body, and generally from any physical facts. The same is possible also in naturalistic (emergentist) versions of dualism.

This initial qualitative profile of an individual human person develops subsequently as a result of complex interactions between its own dispositions and external factors. This process is regulated-conditioned laws of nature – physical, psycho-physical (how states and processes in the brain interact with the mind-consciousness-soul-self) and psychical (regularities within the mind, in relations between mental states), – but this regulation-conditioning can be not strictly deterministic, but include elements of chance like those which, according with the notions of modern physics, occur at the quantum-mechanical microlevel, and also, may be, some other forms of indeterminism.

In particular, connections between such our mental states as beliefs, convictions, feelings, moods, desires, and decisions we make, and our actions may contain considerable elements of indeterminism. Our various mental states may predispose us in various degrees to different decisions and actions, so that this makes probability of some decisions and actions high while probability of some others low; but our decisions and actions are not predetermined unequivocally by preceding states. The different possibilities between which we choose really exist. In not just seems to us that we can act so or otherwise, whereas really we cannot act any other way than we will in fact act. We can really act this way, and can act otherwise. Preceding states (physical and mental) do not determine a choice unequivocally, but determine probabilities of this or that choice. In their turn, those choices we implement become efficient factors which direct changes-development of our persons.

The supposition of incompleteness of determination of mental states – not just as "external" determination by physical processes in the brain, but also as "internal" determination of mental states by other mental states – accords with the "natural" understanding by people of how they make decisions, and to their understanding of the concept of freedom. The opposite, deterministic notion – that a person cannot really act either this or some other way, that every his/her future act is predetermined in advance (from the very moment of the emergence of the Universe – the Big Bang), and cannot be different from what it will in fact turn out to be – is incompatible with that notion on which any decision-making, all the human activity is necessarily based.

It is important to notice also, that the indeterminism of the dynamics of the human mind-self can have a qualitatively different character than that of quantum-mechanical indeterminism or indeterminism in a choice between available known possibilities. This qualitatively different and higher form of indeterminism imparts to it a human (as distinct from quantum-mechanical) character; it is connected with creativity, discovery by a person of new ideas and possibilities. In this context, it is appropriate to mention Karl Popper's ideas.

 

Popper was an adherent of both physical and metaphysical indeterminism.[10]

Physical indeterminism is the view (supported by modern quantum mechanics) according to which not all physical events are predetermined entirely and unequivocally by preceding physical events. Some physical events which have occurred, might not occur. In future, some events may occur, and may not occur. There is a spectrum of possibilities which can be realized. Though in fact only one of them will be realized, until it is realized different possibilities exist really, objectively (not just subjectively, in our imagination and thought, as reflection of the incompleteness of our knowledge). The existence of different possibilities is not our illusion born of the incompleteness of our knowledge (about preceding states of the world and the laws of nature); it has not epistemological, but ontological character; it is a part of how the world really is.

However, Popper noticed that physical indeterminism by itself is not a solution to the problems of human freedom and creativity. It is just a "negative" precondition, a condition of possibility for another type of causality, and also, probably, for another type of indeterminism. For Popper, physical èíäåòåðìèíèçì is important exactly because it leaves a space for non-physical causality, non-physical determination, for the interaction between the three "worlds" – the physical world, the human mind and the world of “objectivated” ideas – scientific theories, works of art, songs, stories, fairy tales, myths, poetry, novels etc. Technical inventions, social institutes, customs, traditions also belong here. This "world-3" is especially important, for only in relation to it the human life obtains a genuinely human character; freedom and creativity are possible only in the interaction between a human person and "world-3".

 

Meditations of the famous American philosopher and psychologist William James[11] are also very much relevant. James contended that it is impossible to prove the truth or falsity of determinism; in this sense, the choice between determinism and indeterminism is a matter of faith. But it needn’t be a groundless, "blind", irrational faith. We have rational grounds to give preference to one of these alternatives, proceeding from moral considerations: which of them creates an acceptable picture of reality making sense of the moral dimension of human life? These James's thoughts have much in common with thoughts of Kant, who argued that we cannot prove by scientific the existence or non-existence of freedom, but moral consciousness (practical reason) demands its existence and, thus, serves as a reason for the belief in it. James argued that determinism is unacceptable, for it denies the way of thinking about our actions which is necessary for human life, viz.: that in a certain situation we really can (could) act either one way or another. From the point of view of determinism it only seems to us, that in this or that situation we can (or could) act somehow otherwise than how we will act (have acted) in fact; really, all our actions are necessarily predetermined by a preceding course of events (totality of the conditions which determine these actions); we just do not know how exactly, and mistakenly take some part of this process of determination for a free choice.

Explaining the causes of domination of determinism among scientists and science-oriented philosophers, James remarked, that determinism expresses "a temper of intellectual absolutism, a demand that the world shall be a solid block, subject to our control – which temper, which demand, the world may not be bound to gratify at all". In contrast, indeterminism "gives us a pluralistic, restless universe, in which no single point of view can ever take in the whole scene; and to a mind possessed of the love of unity at any cost, it will, no doubt, remain forever inacceptable".[12]

But the price for the illusion of deterministic unity and control is too high. Determinism means that everything that happens – including all human decisions and actions – is necessary-inevitable, predetermined by a preceding course of events. In particular, the whole human history and all actions of every human being are unequivocally predetermined by a state of the world before the first human being existed. Laplace’s demon, having the full information about the state of the Universe a second after the Big Bang, could calculate all the events in the Universe after that moment, – in particular, all actions of every human being till our time and afterwards. If someone somewhere has cruelly murdered a person, he/she couldn’t help doing this; it was long ago predetermined that he/she will do it. (On a wider historical scale: Hitler, Stalin and other organizers and executors of mass murders could not act otherwise.) There are no exceptions from the deterministic rule. Such a picture of the world is hardly acceptable.

William James' conclusion is: “...while I freely admit that the pluralism and the restlessness are repugnant and irrational in a certain way, I find that every alternative to them is irrational in a deeper way. ... Whatever difficulties may beset the philosophy of objective right and wring, and the indeterminism it seems to imply, determinism ... contains difficulties that are greater still.... The world is enigmatic enough in all conscience, whatever theory we can take up toward it. The indeterminism I defend, the free-will theory of popular sense based on the judgment of regret, represents that world as vulnerable, and liable to be injured by certain of its parts if they act wrong. And it represents their acting wrong as a matter of possibility or accident, neither inevitable nor yet to be infallibly warded off.”[13]

 

******

In conclusion, I can’t leave without notice V.Vasilyev's comment about “a reference to the fundamental role of the mental "individual"”, which is thought of in accordance with such models as Descartes’ “unity of the thinking Ego, or Kant's "original unity of apperception"”.[14]  Vasilyev objects to such a reference on the following ground:

In our day and age … it seems obvious that this "unified," "self-identical" and "free" Ego is a superficial, not deep-down, phenomenon, a mental superstructure that can by no means be the ontological basis of mental states.[15]

In the same way, an adherent of materialism could declare, without considering arguments of opponents, that in our day and age it seems obvious that mental states are a superficial, not deep-down phenomenon, a mental superstructure that can by no means be ontologically basic. For me, personally, exactly the opposite seems obvious (irrespective of “our day and age”):

1) The Humean idea of mental states without a mental subject – sensations which noone experiences, feelings which noone feels, thoughts which noone thinks, desires which noone desires – is a sheer nonsense. If we admit the existence of mental states, we should admit the existence of the mental subject whose mental states they are. Logically, the concept of a mental subject is primary relative to the concept of mental states; this means that ontologically the mental subject is primary relative to (his/her) mental states (surely, on the condition that they exist). In other words, the mental subject is the ontological basis of mental states. Sensations, feelings, thoughts, desires are not independent entities which can exist by themselves, without being sensations, feelings, thoughts, desires of some mental subject.

2) The mental subject is unified, indivisible, self-identical in that simple and obvious sense that all my (your) sensations, feelings, thoughts, desires are exclusively my (your) sensations, feelings, thoughts, desires, i.e. belong to unconditionally the same mental subject – me (you), my (your) mental self.

A mental subject is not a conventional unit that we pick up out of the whole of reality on some in principle arbitrary considerations, – as in the case with the physical objects, where we can consider as a distinct object any aggregate of atoms, molecules, or macrophysical objects, including those with perpetually changing composition of objects-components (as in the case of live organisms), if such way of individuation is useful for some our purpose or convenient in some context. Separateness/individuality of mental subjects is something unconditionally given. My sensations, feelings, thought processes and desires are unconditionally mine, – it is not that they are conditionally either mine, or belonging to some multitude of "partial" subjects that "inhabit" my brain (a subject S1 has a sensation A, a subject S2 feels B, a subject S3 thinks C, a subject S4 wills D, and a subject SN experiences the illusion that he/she has a sensation A, feels B, thinks C and wills D), or mine together with John, or belonging to the subject-nation named Ukraine.

 

In one of his books, V.Vasilev, with reference to Dereck Parfit, makes a statement that can be interpreted as negation of 2):

“… the identity of a person, as we now know, is rather conditional (to understand the issue of the identity of a person we may resort to a simple analogy: whether we will consider as identical some thing, say, a plasticine cube after we have transformed it into formless mass? On the one hand, no, on the other hand, yes insofar as it is made of the same plasticine; the same with a person: after radical changes of character we can say, on the one hand, that we became other persons, on the other hand – that we remained the same persons insofar as our present existence continues a former stream of consciousness; but the identity of our person in this case is no more substantial, than the identity of plasticine mass in that example.)”[16]

However, this analogy is either mistaken or irrelevant. Surely, if we use the word "person" in the sense of a certain set of character traits, memories, etc., then the identity of a person is just as conditional as the identity of a piece of plasticine. But we are concerned not with the identity of set of character traits, memories, etc., but with the identity of a mental subject. As I have explained in 2), the “individness” and identity of a subject are unconditional, unlike the conditional “individness” and identity of a piece of plasticine.

Let's notice that even if someone says about himself/herself: “I have became entirely another person”, meaning changes of character, values, etc., i.e. of a "person", such a statement necessarily presupposes the identity of the subject-self, in the meaning that is very different from the identity of a "person" (both "persons", the former and the present, belong to the same subject-self), as well as from the identity of a body.

True, a plasticine piece can conditionally be considered as the same “insofar as it is made of the same plasticine”. (Though the sameness of material is not necessary – other physical objects can be considered as the same even after full change of composition. For example, a human or animal body can conditionally be considered as the same throughout the life even if it has retained no single atom that was there at the moment of birth.) However, unlike a plasticine piece, the mental subject is not made of subjective mental states/processes (such “madeness” would mean the absurd idea that subjective mental states can exist on their own, without a subject – a pain that noone feels, subjective thought that noone thinks etc.); it is logically and ontologically primary in relation to them.

The same goes for “a stream of consciousness”. Despite Hume, the concept of "a stream of consciousness” without a mental subject is nonsense. It presupposes that there are certain particles, elements of consciousness that gather into (conditional) streams consist, as it is in all cases of physical streams. If so, it should be clear that particles gathering into streams can also exist on their own; they don’t need streams for their existence; they are ontologically primary in relation to (conditional) streams they form. Application of this approach to consciousness means the absurd idea of subjective mental states that noone subjectively experiences.



[1] "collapse" – the concept of quantum mechanics that means the transformation of a quantum-mechanical wave into microparticles

[2] In fact, these theories are not theories of the splintered mind; they are holistic. So, in Eccles’ theory psychons are only mediators (in my opinion, unneeded) between the mental self and the brain. And Stapp’s theory is not about interaction between the brain and separate experiences, but about interaction between the brain and the mind.

[3] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth; Âàñèëüåâ Â.Â. Òðóäíàÿ ïðîáëåìà ñîçíàíèÿ. Ãëàâà 5; Âàñèëüåâ Â.Â. Ñîçíàíèå è âåùè.

[4] Vasilyev complicates the picture by the theory that the influence of mental states on the brain is actually influence of non-local physical causes on the brain mediated by the mind. (Òðóäíàÿ ïðîáëåìà ñîçíàíèÿ. – Ñ.223-227; Ñîçíàíèå è âåùè. – Ñ.136-140, 177-179) As a result, the conception of Vasilyev (which he calls ‘local interactionism’) turns out to be quasi-interactionism: “… genuine causes of behaviour have a physical nature. Though … mental states do not have direct influence on behaviour and, hence, are deprived of causal efficiency, they nevertheless retain causal relevance, being necessary ontological conditions of the realisation of non-local physical causality.” (Ñîçíàíèå è âåùè. – Ñ.178-179) I will confine the discussion to the issue of determinism, without dwelling on such extravagant aspects of Vasilyev’s conception.

[5] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth. – p. 56.

[6] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth. – p. 56-57.

[7] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth. – p. 56-57.

[8] Popper K. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. – P.39, 249;

Popper K. The Open Society and Its Enemies. Vol.2. – P.262-263.

[9] Popper K. Evolutionary Epistemology

[10] Popper K. Of Clouds and Clocks;

Popper K. Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics

[11] James W. The Dilemma of Determinism.

[12] James W. The Dilemma of Determinism. – ðð.360, 364.

[13] James W. The Dilemma of Determinism. – ð.364.

[14] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth. – p. 63.

[15] Vasilyev V. Brain and Consciousness: Exits from the Labyrinth. – p. 63.

[16] Âàñèëüåâ Â.Â. Ñîçíàíèå è âåùè. – ñ.166

 

[Return to Content]

[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]