[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]

[Return to Content]

 

…materialism is the philosophy of the subject who forgets to take account of himself.

Arthur Schopenhauer[1]

 

Many people, including a past self of mine, have thought that they could simultaneously take consciousness seriously and remain a materialist. ...this is not possible, and for straightforward reasons. ...One might say: You can’t have your materialist cake and eat your consciousness too.

Temperamentally, I am strongly inclined toward materialist reductive explanation, and I have no strong spiritual or religious inclinations. For a number of years, I hoped for a materialist theory; when I gave up on this hope, it was quite reluctantly. It eventually seemed plain to me that these conclusions were forced on anyone who wants to take consciousness seriously. Materialism is a beautiful and compelling view of the world, but to account for consciousness, we have to go beyond the resources it provides.

David Chalmers[2]

 

…one should trust ... pluralistic discord over systematic harmony... If arguments or systematic theoretical considerations lead to results that seem intuitively not to make sense, or if a neat solution to a problem does not remove the conviction that the problem is still there, or if a demonstration that some question is unreal leaves us still wanting to ask it, then something is wrong with the argument and more work needs to be done …

…to create understanding, philosophy must convince. That means it must produce or destroy belief, rather then merely provide us with a consistent set of things to say...

Thomas Nagel[3]


Preface

This book deals with the mind-body problem – the problem of the relation between the mind as the realm of subjective experiences and the body (brain) as part of physical reality (matter) – or, to be more exact, the problem of the nature of the bearer-subject of mental states and processes (feelings, experiences, emotions, awareness, thinking, wishes, etc.), the mental self, and its relation to the body (the brain).

The problem consists primarily of questions of the most vital importance for every sentient and thinking person, such as:

  What am I? What is the human self? Is it (am I) just a complicated aggregate of atoms moving and interacting due to physical laws? Or is it (am I) something nonmaterial (a soul)?

These questions entail others, of no less importance:

  Is it possible for us (our selves-souls) to continue personal existence after physical death? (Also, is it possible that we were existing before our current earthly life?) Is it possible that there is personal immortality?

Many philosophers of different (including opposite) worldviews considered this as the most important philosophical problem.

An influential 19-th century German philosopher-materialist Friedrich Engels estimated the problem (although giving it rather a misleading title – the "question … concerning the relation of thinking and being"[4]) as “the great basic question of all philosophy, especially of modern philosophy”. And he explained: “From the very early times when men, still completely ignorant of the structure of their own bodies, under the stimulus of dream apparitions, came to believe that their thinking and sensation were not activities of their bodies, but of a distinct soul which inhabits the body and leaves it at death – from this time, men have been driven to reflect about the relation between this soul and the outside world. If, upon death, it took leave of the body and lived on, there was no occasion to invent yet another distinct death for it. Thus arose the idea of immortality...”[5]

On the other hand, consider the statement of a Spanish novelist and philosopher Miguel de Unamuno: “…the longing not to die, the hunger for personal immortality … is the affective basis of all knowledge and the personal inward starting-point of all human philosophy, wrought by a man and for men.”[6]

Despite the diametrically opposite attitudes towards the possibility of personal immortality, Engels and Unamuno agreed in the view that the belief in personal immortality is antirational. In the Õ²Õ–ÕÕ centuries, not only materialists, but also many thinkers who approved the idea of personal immortality, thought that it is contrary to reason – that to believe in immortality is to defy reason.

My own meditation on the problem has resulted (long before I started serious study of the relevant philosophical literature) in the different conclusion: materialism is false; subjective feelings, experiences, consciousness cannot be physical processes; I, my self as the subject of mental states and processes – that something which feels, experiences, wishes, and thinks – is neither my body nor my brain but something non-physical, which corresponds to the concept of a soul. Furthermore, it is natural to suppose the possibility of its existence after physical death and, may be, before this life (my reasons for this conclusion were roughly the same as those discussed in Section 3 “The Zombie Argument”). The subsequent study in the philosophical literature on the problem (most of all, the arguments of Karl Popper, John Beloff, Thomas Nagel, David Chalmers, Frank Jackson, John Searle) has strengthened this conclusion.

Generally, the decade of the 1970 started a new tendency in the philosophy of mind: many reputable nonreligious scientifically oriented philosophers, who are "temperamentally inclined toward materialism" (see the confession of David Chalmers in the epigraph to this book), arrived at the conclusion that materialism is incapable to account for the mind, consciousness, subjectivity – for the fact that we are beings who subjectively feel, have experiences, and are aware – instead of being automata which automatically, without any subjective feeling and awareness, execute some “biological program” (however complicated).

Many philosophers of the second half of the ÕÕ century who have realized the inadequacy of materialism and defended some form of dualism or pluralism (see the Glossary: dualism, pluralism) nevertheless avoided the traditional concept of soul. I consider this avoidance as a manifestation of the fear of accusations in the gravest “deadly sins” against science – mysticism and obscurantism. One such philosopher (to whom I am greatly indebted), Karl Popper, has finished his article “Language and the Body-Mind Problem” with the remark: “The fear of obscurantism (or of being judged an obscurantist) has prevented most anti-obscurantists from saying such things as these. But this fear has produced, in the end, only obscurantism of another kind.”[7] Let me explain this remark as I understand it.

During the last several centuries, in the process of struggle against religious mysticism and obscurantism, scientists and science-oriented philosophers have got under strong influence of materialism. This doctrine pretends to scientific status, and its adherents are prone to label whatever has some resemblance to religion or conflicts with materialism as mysticism and obscurantism. Quite a few philosophers and scientists who see the inadequacy of materialism are afraid to state their view, lest they should be accused of obscurantism. This means that in the modern scientific-philosophical community, religious obscurantism is replaced with materialistic obscurantism. I hope this book will contribute to its overcoming.

It is important not to be afraid to call things by their names. In particular, the concept of soul has to be rehabilitated. To ascertain the soul’s existence, we need neither mystics nor appeal to religious authorities; all we need is contained in our everyday experience. There are very weighty rational arguments which show that the mind (consciousness), the self, is something non-physical, distinct from the body, although in intimate connection-interaction with it. This “something non-physical, distinct from the body, although in intimate connection-interaction with it” was always called 'soul'.

There is yet another modern “scientific taboo” (closely associated with the avoidance of the concept of soul) that I trespass in this book – discussion of the possibility of afterlife (J.Schwartz and S.Begley remark that it is considered sort of indecent – “something no self-respecting scientist is supposed to do in public”[8]).

Many prominent scientists were not afraid to oppose quasi-scientific materialistic stereotypes. For example, the outstanding neurosurgery scientist Wilder Penfield, the founder of modern neurophysiology Charles Sherrington[9], the Nobel Prize winner in neurophysiology John Eccles, the Nobel Prize winner in physics Eugene Wigner[10].

The book is intended not just for professional philosophers, but for thinking people without special philosophical education who strive to understand the world and their own selves. ² have tried my best to expound clearly the main existing views and arguments on the problem and to give an account of my own view and its rationales, avoiding unnecessary technical terms. Those terms which I considered expedient are explained where they first appear and in the Glossary at the end of the book.

 

 

‘Gender-inclusive language’ notification

When talking about abstract persons, I use

feminine pronouns in sections 1, 3, 5, 7, 9, 11, 13, 15, 17,

the second appendix in Book 1, and the first appendix in Book 2;

masculine pronouns in sections 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 14, 16

the first appendix in Book 1, and the second appendix in Book 2.

The order is reversed when talking of gods, demons, ghosts, aliens, robots, etc.

 



[1] Schopenhauer A. The World as Will and Idea. – Vol. 2. – p. 176

[2] Chalmers D. The Conscious Mind. – ð. 168, õiv.

[3] Nagel T. Mortal Questions. Preface. – pp. x-xi.

[4] Engels uses “thinking and being” as synonymous to “mind and matter”. He equates being (i.e. all that exists) with matter from the very outset and thereby crudely begs the question.

[5] Engels F. Ludwig Feuerbach & the End of Classical German Philosophy. (Italicizing mine)

[6] Unamuno M. The Tragic Sense of Life.

[7] Popper K. Language and the Body-Mind Problem. – p. 402.

[8] Schwartz J., Begley S. The Mind & The Brain. – ð. 45.

[9] “That our being should consist of two fundamental elements offers I suppose no greater inherent improbability than that it should rest on one only” (C.Sherrington, quot. by: Popper K., Eccles J. The Self and Its Brain. – ð. 62.)

[10] “It is interesting from a psychological-epistemological point of view that, although consciousness is the only phenomenon for which we have direct evidence, many people deny its reality. The question "If all that exists are some complicated chemical processes in your brain, why do you care what those processes are?" is countered with evasion. One is led to believe that ... the word "reality" does not have the same meaning for all of us.” (E.Wigner, quot. by: Schwartz J., Begley S. The Mind & The Brain. – ð. vii.)

[Return to Content]

[Return to Dmitry Sepety’s Personal Page]